Stein von Reusch
P A S S I O N
WITHOUT HATRED OR
GREED;
RESONATING OVER
DANCERS;
CREATING NEW
PHYSICS
CONTENTS
* Awakening
* What is science
and why should we bother?
* Can metaphysics
be refutable? On mysticism and rationality
* Modes of
questioning
* Youthfulness and
the theory of happiness
* Paul Feyerabend
on Popper
* Ethics and
worldviews
* The role of the
body in painting
* How to listen to
the voice of intuition
* Sketch of a
mathematical insight into infinity
* Colors in
painting
* The role of
slenderness and the question of whether health is
attractive
* Passion, energy,
sex and freedom from attachments
* Macroscopic
nonlocality
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
AND SOURCES
Special
thanks and acknowledgements to Frans Widerberg, who is one of
Norway's greatest
painters, and to Aasa, his wife. About questions of mind, psyche and
quanta, on issues of art and insight, on freedom from conclusions and
the spirit of exploration: he has been a teacher.
For
this book, published in 2004, also special
thanks to: Elisabeth and Nina Van Waagen, Charlotte and Siri B
Bergloeff, Margaret
Hemsen, Monica Emilie Herstad, Sarel and David Bohm, Kjell Bugge,
Therese Ellefsen, Kristen Nygaard, Kit-Fai and Arne Naess, Liliane and
Pauline Heyzer Fan,
Henrik B Tschudi, my parents Else and Stein, my
sisters Kristin and Marianne.
For
the physics
part, hundreds of standard classical texts on the
physics laboratory studies of the twentieth century I assume as
necessary background to make much sense of what is written there; just
spend some weeks or months at a physics library and get into the
vocabulary. It makes little sense to make any source reference here but
the humor and lucidity of some of Richard Feynman's lectures and
descriptions of some part of quantum physics are often liked by many,
though I think he is a bit thin on nonlocality: that can be made up by
readings of Nick Herbert's popular physics books, by the reading of J S
Bell 'Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Theory', and by the reading
of the discussions between Bohr and Einstein; as well as a deep reading
of everything David Bohm published, supplementing with readings by the
older Louis de Broglie, Heisenberg, Schroedinger and other forefathers
of the physics of twentieth century. A book which it might be
interesting to read, especially if you insert a small word, namely the
word 'not', inside nearly all its crucial statements, is Stephen
Hawking's, "A brief History of Time". My own understanding of
Einstein's work was greatly improved by my 'sitting in' on a number of
conversations between Arne Naess and Oeyvind Groen when they made the
book on the mathematics of general relativity theory; however my
thoughts about Einstein's work is, in some ways, rather different from
how the eminent physicist Groen presents it, I think.
SOURCES
include
what I will call 'reference books', not that I use them
as an authority to be quoted but they have helped provide a vocabulary
and emphasized a number of important insights so as to provide a whole
horizon of meaning with which to investigate any particular problem in
this book. I have already mentioned, but let me do so again, K. R.
Popper, "The Open Society and its Enemies", volume I and II, first
published in 1945 by RKP, London; fifth edition (revised) 1966, RKP
Paperback, ISBN 0-7100-4626-X. Let me say right at once that I find
this a much more mature book than his earlier "The Logic of Scientific
Discoveries", and I find 'refutability' a more insightful and
penetrating concept than his earlier 'falsifibility', although Popper
continued to revise the earlier book and, to some extent, also
continued to use the falsifibility notion. In addition, hundreds of
classical articles on physics form the background of this work; some of
them are collected in books; and some of them are books (such as
'Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Theory' by J S Bell).
Then
I should
mention a couple of books which is a constant source of
inspiration and meaning though I haven't read them for a long time and
do not have them around me at present, so I will not give too precise
information about their publishing issues -- they are however rather
considered 'classics' in many connections so they should be easy to
find. The first is J. Krishnamurti, "Freedom from the Known", edited by
Mary Lutyens, ca 1970. The second is D. Bohm, "Wholeness and the
Implicate Order", London, 1980. I should also mention the book by Arne
Naess
called "The Pluralist and Possibilist Aspect of the Scientific
Enterprise", perhaps around 1960. This book draws a number of
implications from such attitudes as also characterized K.R.Popper if I
am not mistaken.
Additionally,
--
for this or that theme, in free sequence -- I must
mention key conversations with Julie Oredam, Ane Graff, Ida Nathalie
Kierulf, Gunvor Iversen, Gunnar Lovhoiden, Odd Grann, Karine Huseby,
Warren Brodey, Thomas d'Arcy Shepherd, Astri Kleppe, Holger
Bech-Nielsen, Anette Krumhardt, Jens Hvass, Espen Holm, Sandra de Zilwa
and Sonia
de Zilawa, Live Slang, Kari Dybwad, Jon-Roar Bjorkvold, Arne Nordheim,
Kari Bu, Buffy Lundgren,
Ingvild Wegger Karlsen, Hege Brenden, Basil Hiley, Chris Dewdney,
Ingrid Solbjorg, Alicia
Kelley, Petter Noklebye, Nicholas Hagger,
Lakshmi Chayapathi, Herman R Jervel, David Lorimer, Kristen Nygaard,
Cathrine
Bryhn, Oyvind Groen, Tiril Morsund, Isabel Watson, Sofie Olsen, Anna
Kathinka
Evans, Chong Ming, Leah Garland, Johan Reusch, Kolbjoern Braa, Heidi
Ekstrom, Per Sand, Ladislav Kohbach,
Erika Christina Rieber-Mohn, Ramman Patek, Catharina Arganti, Ari Behn,
Johannes
Hansteen, Sven-Oluf Soerensen, Angelisa Miller, Jorgen Cappelen, Espen
Holm,
Marcia d'Olivera, Tordis Dalland Evans, Mari
Midtstigen, Aage Borg-Andersen, Konrad and Anne-Lise
Magnus, Bertrand Besige, Kari Dybwad, Roman Bieler, Kim
Naergaard, Camilla
Coucheron, Raymond Strano, David Schonberg, Jon Bing and Camilla
Clausen. Thanks also to conversations with Marianne's kids, Christine
Maria, Johan, Jan, Karin and Katharina, and to their father, Jan.
Thanks also to some key
conversations with Francis Steen, now at UCLA as professor in cognitive
science; Okay, I already know of some fifty more names I
should add. I apologize that this list simply MUST be incomplete.
Thanks all the universe!
THANKS
Music and
music movies by Gwen Stephany, Joss Stone, Bob Marley,
Bjork, Alicia Keys, Jan Garbarek, ... J S Bach, Carl Phillip Emanuel
Bach (etc), Mozart, ... Ska, Rai, Reggae etc, ... Arvo Part, Jan
Garbarek, Karl Maria von Weber, Chopin, ..., Beatles, Pink Floyd, Jeff
Buckley, Maria Arradondo, Christina Aguilera, Keith Jarret, Ani de
Franco, Alanis Morriset, The Muse, Portishead, etc, etc etc ....
THANKS
graphical
work and paintings by Frans Widerberg, Picasso,
Salvador Dali, Tamara de Lempicka, Frida Kahlo, Gustav Klimt
*
Awakening
The freedom to be alive and dance, to do yoga in the morning, to work
by oneself and come to the realizations of the wholeness of the
universe, this is in its undogmatic, open, gurufree forms something of
what the spiritual life is all about.
Let us step outside of traditions and gently challenge all people who
try to set themselves up as spiritual authorities, so that we are
dialogue partners in the great conversations which life has with
itself: we are life.
We are alive, and aliveness has a greater depth of importance than any
idea, any rite, any ritual, any culture.
In the great battles between intentions, let us not merely compare how
much we like this or that style, but ask: what has more life in it?
Where is the vitality? What blossoms with energy? What has radiance?
For life, radiance, is the all-powerful, the all-intelligent, that
which goes beyond all the mechanical.
When our minds are awake to all this, then we dance over the hills,
nothing is a tough problem, we can see the joke of existence, the humor
of sexuality, and have utter freedom from attachment and ego even as we
entertain the greatest ecstasies which life can offer.
These ecstasies do not belong to the cage of seeking experience, or
seeking intensity. They belong to the quietness within which
reverberates and give depth of meaning to even the subtlest of
harmonies.
We must challenge what we think is 'boring', for the ego lives on
dividing fun from boredom and seeking fun, not seeing that its shallow
fun is devoid of the vitality which could give a greater ecstasy, that
of love and compassion, than its experience-seeking.
I am not against seeking experience; let us travel much, and be
generous in our interactivity economies, so that we see people, meet
dialogue partners of all backgrounds, and feel the essential unity of
all humankind beyond any stupid division into 'race' or 'religion' or
'color' or anything like that. Humankind is born out of a greater
universe and living nature and in the wholeness of all that, as sensed
in our hearts, as felt in our meditative minds, as shown in our great
energic meditative arts, and as danced in the greatest and most
beautiful of ddances, we are also most aware of ourselves. We are not
in the situation of having to limit the sense of life; no, as the ego
dissolves we see that the doors open and we can go through them,
feeling that the universe is a garden, our garden.
And yet, when we come down from this exalted state and meet the
incredible parroting and brutality of humanity at least as humanity as
been in its past, we must face up to the question of giving priority to
something rather than something else. I will not give a recipe, I will
not say: give priority to this rather than that, abhor that, support
this, but let us ask: what can we do to recreate the highest senses of
love in our being, the highest forms of intuition in our hearts, the
highest clarities in our minds, indeed, enlightenment in the very
essence of our being, each day anew? Even each hour anew?
If the mind is vast landscape in which all beings exist, then absolute
condemnation of any being would be a conflict within ourselves with
ourselves. Whether we like it or not, interconnectedness may be the
strong big fact, the Fact before fact.
So what we can do? What can we do, if the ways and habits of our days
are so that we go around with brains which are merely active in
monotonic ways? What can we do to awaken ourselves?
If there were countless libraries of books of the P.G.Wodehouse type,
then limitless humor would open up in our minds whenever we wanted.
Alas, there aren't that many of that type of books, and jokes of the
past may not work in the future. The meditation technique of yesterday
may not be the requirement of this day.
In enquiring into the activation of joy, meditative joy, tantric joy,
we are asking for something other than mere identity, we are asking for
something other than a recipe, we are asking: what is it that is always
new? That is always flowering? The rama which always creates? The
fountain which is always fresh?
Obviously, no limited set of words, no Bible or set of dogmas, no poem
or fixed equation, can be limitlessly new. The nerves of our minds
demand the new sunrise, the new valley, the new face, the new touch,
the new behaviour, the new gait, the new look, the new gestalt, the new
sense of life, the new form, we must be artists, we must wrap ourselves
in the newness of creationship, of making things according to our
hearts each day anew, and yet that may not be enough: hooked on making
new things we may still perpetuate patterns ingrained deep in our
preconscious minds.
So what are we to do?
If no technique can always work, if no set of ambitions are always
fulfilling, and if we perhaps feel that we are silently merely carrying
out the hypnosis installed in us from environment, parents, peers or
other elements of the past, how are we going to unwrap the new flower
of the mind of this moment? Not by drugs, surely; not by alcohol, which
destroys the finer subtlety and sensitivity of the nonlocal kind inside
our heads; not by brainless addiction to sports; not by the chase of
winning games. We are asking: how can we go beyond the 'how', how can
we find the freshness of the life of the universe when our nerves are
not abundant with it, but when we have perhaps some kind of conflict or
pattern or habit or something -- something or other -- which keeps us
back from it?
In short, how can we uncondition ourselves?
This is a real scientific question also. Science, apart from what may
be practised in the name of science, may be about going beyond the
self, touching reality with thoughts, not just having stale reactions.
Thoughts which are alive with silence can come from questioning, from
dialogue, from listening to dialogically oriented friendly person who
is giving talks.
We can write a question to ourselves in one voice and answer it in
another voice, the plurality of voices being true to our being, for we
are not but one, but many. And the many are whole, the many are aspects
of greater wholeness that flows through our minds in each moment.
This wholeness is ripe with indications of what happens in the future
about the life of us all: it is a wholeness which teaches us what to do
before we have experience of it. It suggests tentative rules, open
plans, free dispositions for actions so that we can dream through the
consequences, feel the karma, enjoy the reading of the synchronicties,
and relate to them so that we get information we could not possibly get
from the past.
So we are asking: can intelligence, an intelligence not limited by mere
experience, be awakened in our minds? Can it be awakened by a process
in which we challenge our nonawakening, each day anew?
It is like asking, what is health? And the answer of health involves
not just a reference to the fullness of the slender flexible
yoga-active dancing creating laughing body, free from shame as to its
sexuality, enjoying the wholeness of buddhahood, but it also refers to
the willingness of this body to stand firm and defend, by a defensive
dance as it were, this wholeness in the meeting with the various forms
of challenges as pollutions, infections etc. So health involves
perception. The immune aspect of the body -- I do not think the word
'system' should be applied to any living process -- the immune aspect
or process in the body is constantly perceiving. This perception is
part of health.
So is it possible to regender perception in us in each day?
But then, what is the language of perception?
I have been thinking about the question of language recently, stepping
out of the hope that any language can be ultimate. I love English for
its freedom from cultural bias -- at least a relative freedom, for it
is able to convey something of the spirit of Pali or Sanskrit, ancient
Greek or modern Hebrew, Mandarin or Javanese, as well as logic, as of
Kurt Goedel or Alan Turing, -- something of all this can be conveyed if
we do not insist on having an English that conforms too much to any
standard of syntax, semantics or spelling. Let us play with English,
now that it is becoming more and more that which the Esperanto-people
sought to make Esperanto into being: a language which is the ownership
of no cult, no clan, no aristocracy.
And yet, what is it that a language does with us, with regard to
perception? In thinking about this, while walking: something which I
like to do, for walking involves some many other mind functions and
body functions than mere thought, so that only a few questions can
present themselves and few open ideas might come, and they may be
saturated with the freshness of walking and the synchronicities of
people and birds and so on who you encounter. Most of this book has
been created and recreated in this way. As a last chapter, you will
find a rather talkative and overly repetitive introduction to a theory
which actually might be a brilliant one...and it has come through a lot
of walks, and a lot of, eh, well, sex also: for I feel that sex engages
the mind in evernew ways and it is part of a healthy dance of yogic
living.
So how can language relate to our perception? How can we use language
to aid perception? And what is it that happens when a language prevents
perception? For in some languages, there are certain words or even
concepts that can hardly be expressed: what does this do to the minds?
Surely, a language must not inject itself into that which should be a
perceptive thought.
Surely, a language must have a transparency.
Surely, a language is only a language insofar as it is fully open,
completely free to relate any kind of perception at all.
Is it not so that a language can only be said to be a language where it
allows us to be fully honest to our perception?
And in this way, we can say of socalled culturally biased languages
that in some way that are not languages. They are merely the
repetitions of stale attitudes or conformity to nonperceptive ideas.
So to communicate, not just with other people, but with ourselves, and
not just with ourselves as persons, but with ourselves as
multidimensional spiritual beings with minds having no known limits or
depths, we need true language activities, with true language elements
which are truly open.
We need, as the Buddha, to be able to say: maybe A is B, maybe A is not
B, maybe A is both B and not B, maybe A is neither B nor not B, and
maybe A is entirely different from all of the earlier options!
We need to be able to say, and feel: reality, actuality, 'what is', is
so much more than we think. More even than this thought.
Explore, explore, explore! Dance with attention to evernew questions,
and regard no stale answer as given! I personally feel good about
life-welcoming affirmations, about watching the flowers and the pretty
girls, and painting them too, and listening to good music and living
with harmoniously uplifting ecstatic type of symbols in and around
myself. But surely, without the challenge of asking a question afresh
and answering it for myself or with another without any reference to
any teacher whatsoever, Buddha, Jesus, Krishna, Muhammad, Lao-Tse, or
any other -- entirely without any reference -- and entirely without any
other drug except coffee (which I adore, together with vitamin pills)
-- without the challenge of fresh dialogue, the mind is not on. To be
on one's beam, to get the mind up and running and feeling silent, to go
faster than one's own ego so as to go completely silent and be utterly
rich with the sense of the infinite and the eternal, we must engage in
creative meditative questioning, questioning all and everything and
never ever stop! We need the questioning, we need it strongly, we need
it as a culture of awakening, a culture of enlightenment which has no
prejudice whatsoever.
In that spirit I submit this summary, which is a word to convey how I
feel about this book, this summary which might indicate some senses,
some possibilities, some directions, some lines of reasoning to get
something of the foundation a little bit straight so as to encourage
the enjoyment of personal exploration of the most important and big
questions in life every day anew.
When we engage in enquiry, we create art, we create the art of
discourse, the art of insight, the art of awareness, the art of being
in tune with a life which transcends the predictions of the past: the
art of being new and being harmonious in relation to whatever is at
hand. This is the art of having facts not just opinions, not just stale
reactions or fixed ideas; facts which come freshly as flowers from each
enquiry every day anew, which gives energy to our dance, energy and
modelling freshness to our yoga, energy and insight to our
communications, and a feeling of vastness not just in space but also in
duration in which we see all life is infinitely valuable and worthy of
the highest passion of protection beyond all hatred and beyond all
greed.
This enquiry we can give to each other, as air, as dance, as music, for
free. In India, and I love the feeling I have of what India is at its
best, though I cannot say much for its guru-tradition nor its banning
of sexuality between free independent women and men, -- but I love the
sense of India as the explorative ancient country, or continent, which
fostered some of the most mindful creations in humanity, in some of the
most beautiful of recorded spoken languages, four and five and eight
thousand years before Europe began with its dilletantic philosophying,
leading to the vulgar materlism which science has helped bringing about.
The enquiry in Europe lead however (and I am grateful for Astri Kleppe
for insisting in this to me before I saw it clearly myself) women to
achieve a liberation through the materalistic kind of equality which
also the French revolution brought through as an axiom of society.
The materialistic kind of equality is pleasantly bored and open as to
what metaphysics a person prefers, it considers it nonsense anyway.
As a reaction to this anti-metaphysical streak, many people influenced
by the European and North-American standards of materialism have sought
to find elements in less materialistic cultures, and sometimes this has
happened in a way which is characterised by an attitude which J.
Krishnamurti labelled as 'gullible'. Let us not be gullible -- that is,
let us not easily fall prey to belief. Let us be sceptical and rational
about every element of every ideology, and through this rationality
come to greater and greater intuitions. Indeed, Karl R Popper, though
rather anti-metaphysical (see discussions on this in a book, where I
challenge his grounds for it), defines rationality as intuitions which
are checked, in contrast to intuitions 'gone wild'.
It is not lazy nor sloppy nor soft-minded to pick the best of each
culture and join together. It is the only right and decent thing to do
for a serious individual. We must take the equality of man and woman
and the freedom for the individual to go against the idiotic
tribalistic clank-like loyality to family which is projected as Law in
old cultures. We must take the best of this materialism and yet
challenge its non-metaphysical aspects, and do so using, in fact, the
best of the science that brought about materialism in the first place.
In doing so, we can engender completely rejuvenatingly happy free kinds
of societies in which some of the rigmarole of education is turned
around. This is heavy work and so with this book you may be able to
jump ahead a couple of decades of personal work; this book contains
elements, especially in the last chapter, in which the best of science
is extracted in a way which preserves much of its rational original
ground and brought together with a lofty view of the reality of
interconnectedness between each living being -- including you yourself
-- and absolutely everything around you without any limits whatsoever.
This has been attempted by a number of writers with varying degree of
success. The Tao of Physics attempted so on a poetic level, but was
brushed off by many other scientists as superficial. David Bohm with
his Wholeness and the Implicate Order did so in a far more subtle way,
but not so easy to understand, nor very clear as to what in fact is the
human reality of this interconnectedness -- though it may perfectly
well exist on a microscopic level involving electrons and such. We are
made of electrons and so on and so forth but we need to have a clearer
view of the relationship between the macroscopic nonlocality or
interconnectedness (nonlocality being a word from physics indicating a
relationship of an immediate kind between anything and anything else
even separated in time, perhaps).
In biology, Rupert Sheldrake, and also Ken Wilber and others, have
postulated, along with Goethe and Steiner, certain similarity
resonances and the like, which could be part of a real spirituality.
However they have not strongly and clearly related this to any
particular essential question of empirical quantum physics, as I have
done here; besides, I lack in these approaches -- and that is true for
Erwin Laszlo's writings also -- a realisation of the emphasis not just
on similarities but also on contrasts, and not just in the present
moment or with regard to the past, but with regard to the future.
In short, there is some work before this book undone, to put it
immodestly, but humbly felt.
I could go on and on detailing particular ways of exploring the mind,
freeing oneself from conditioning and so on: but since this book in any
case has a finite number of pages and a finite number of words (it
appears, though I have left page numbers out), I have rather felt it
important to give a fresh wind of practical conceptual orientations,
more like a dictionary than like a story. For stories can be read and
tossed away but dictionaries flow through and on due to the openness of
interconnectivity and interactivity in meaning, and I intend to free
myself from the need to write further books after this, and after the
five or ten or more electronic books available on my website yoga4d.com
(or the corresponding item if you read this book in an intergalactic
networking situations; if there is a search option there, search on
'stein von reusch' ;)). Together, all these texts provide a solid
foundation for nonfundamentalistic dialogue with oneself under a
variety of circumstances in such a way that it is likely to work out
and not lead to any problems.
For myself, I have a good strong background in a healthy family and
plenty of good thinkers around me during growing-up period, so I have
never had a trouble with my mind but always sustained the dialogical
spirit even when I have pushed my mind to the limits by not sleeping
for a week under stressing circumstances -- such experiments showed me,
however, that sleep is the great sanity-creating factor and that lack
of sleep easily induces every kind of psychotic-like state in which it
becomes more and more critical that the proper dialogical foundation
habe been laid for the mind to carry it out. Even with such a
foundation, I sometimes experienced that some of the nervousness
created in lack of sleep period became like a cold or flu which had to
be fought of in the following days or week. For people under even
greater stress, especially if they have a weak foundation or are apt to
become dogmatic, things may flip over: please watch your own limits
even as you push them. Having said that, there is infinite grace in
changing sleep patterns for a period while also experimenting with
meditation, trance, sex, enquiry, writing, and dance, in a way which is
free from drugs and alcohol, but full of good vitamin supplies and food
concentrates: this can elevate some of the dormant brain structures to
be part of your senses of life in an elevated way forever after.
Those who have never experienced the ecstasy of enquiry during
sleeplessness have something in line for them: be careful, but do it!
It is a fantastic openness of mind. Now Manhattan as the central and
most active and most interesting part of New York City somehow, for me,
is a metaphor of this energetic state of awakened mind, which is sort
of running faster than its own ego and therefore has come to a more
honest state which is also more silent -- a mixture of contradictions
echoed in such masterful poems as those by Walt Whitman and much later
by the man behind Planet News.
Compassion may suddenly come through, when you realize that the state
of mind which has pervaded humanity for thousands of years is dense
with self-centeredness and that most people are happily unaware of it
-- happily, that is, at a level of self-description, perhaps, though in
their eyes the immense sadness of not realizing their inner vitality
more fully is shown to all who can see.
I say, English has become a language able to convey spiritual emotions
beyond any dogma, beyond any religion, at least after William James'
The Varieties of Religious Experience and Bertrand Russell's The
Conquest of Happiness and his masterful (but atheistic) History of
Western Philosophy. There is nothing you cannot say to yourself in
English, even if English is far far away from your mother tongue: I
think you will find that it washes through your feelings with
perceptions in a way which an ethnic language cannot do easily in the
same way, unless perhaps this is a language infused with undogmatic
buddhism like the language of the Thais.
Explore, enquire, activate the mind and the body along with it also
sexually, for there is no category that can be avoided in the great
conversation and activation of the most harmonious essence of what it
means to be alive. Aliveness is the greater tree which sees the cycles
of birth and death but which does not merely limit itself to see those
cycles as essential. As I see Buddha's teachings -- and I would not
call myself a 'buddhist' because of the dogmas I have sometimes felt
that those who easily call themselves a 'buddhist' may associate
themselves with -- they are not against life but against shallow
self-centered identification with a fragment of life. A buddhist is
life-lover, nonviolently so, and being a life-lover means loving
sexuality when it is scientifically as well as psychologically and
spiritually clear that sexuality is inherent in the fullness of
flowering life. But a buddhist is against the attachment to piece of
sexuality, or the incorporation of pleasure into a particular form,
because, ultimately, the buddhist have an insight that such attachment
is the essence of illusion, suffering and destruction of life. It is by
virtue of the compassion with all living beings that attachment is seen
as dangerous. But the buddhist must also then not be attachment to
buddhism or to an organisation or to a teacher; for by virtue of this
greater insight into wholeness, there is no attachment at all which is
the ripe fullness of awareness. And this awareness is easily also
sexual because the sexual, in its humor, reveals the life spirit to
itself and rejuvenates it.
So the engagement in sexuality without an ego is part of the immense
and beautiful and open challenge to the serious spiritual individual,
man as woman, and of course we must realize that it is an art not to
create children while having lots of sex, because children is a total
giving-over of oneself to a new life process in a way which demands
decades of generosity without limits. So in not creating children, and
in having sex, and not in not creating attachments, we must see the
danger of exclusive agreements on partnership sex, because in such
circumstances the sex can foster a personality element which is nothing
but a new ego, though perhaps shared somewhat between two persons. Add
to this the biological reaction for the young girl who knows that she
might get a baby -- I mean, the genes know that she might get a baby --
and the genes will naturally leap out and attach themselves in a deep
and spiritual way to a male if that male is alone there in giving her
sperm, put bluntly. What I am pointing out here is that it is
rediculous, even disasterous, to condemn sexuality between girls and
between two girls and a man, because human beings are sexual beings and
they need a free sexuality by virtue of uphelding the life currents in
their bodies in a yogic sense. This natural necessity should not lead
to attachment, and when a girl feels the presence of another girl in
the sexual experience, she has an in-born response so as to act so that
babies are not created and the genes know that this is not a situation
which is apt to lead to a permanent male provider. The very presence of
other girls in group sexuality creates a sense of freedom from
attachment and one must train oneself to accept such situations and go
beyond any petty comparison which might limit the situation.
Seen in this light, the sexual freedom of materialism is holding within
itself a fantastic promise of real spirituality when it is combined
with enquiry into the freedom from the ego, and also from reckless
pursuit of games and foolish addictions such as cannabis. The hippie
movement, in its best essence, was neither about drugs, nor about gurus
or politics, but about the combination of sex and spirituality. To give
a greater realization of the importance not to have drugs in the brain,
it would do good to add physics to the picture, as here presented or in
some other nondogmatic refutable manner which allows interconnectedness
to be seen rationally as a ground for the relationship between an open
upcoming future and the dialogic present. The freedom from dogmatism is
easier if we trust our own intuitions, trust our own minds, trust our
own feelings of enquiry, and also seen the sadness, the suffering, the
sorrow, of what dogmatism leads humanity into as wars, terrors, crimes,
illness, epidemics, pollution, destruction of forests etc etc.
Dogmatism and its self-centred coldness, and such idiotic manifests as
Ayn Rand's Virtue of Selfishness, lead to a perpetuation of the closed
mind which is the antithesis of the intent of this whole enterprise and
joy, which is the ground of this book and the talks I constantly gives
and so on.
So I offer the suggestion that we welcome porn and think of it as a
beginning spirituality in which beauty is the intent beyond personal
ownership; in which violence is not accepted, not considered as
interesting as part of the sexuality; but in which sex of all kinds, as
long as it is healthy and not based on coercion or drugs or lies, is
welcomed, in all areas of society, in all areas of thinking, in all
areas of life. I do not think that all porn is art but I do think that
all art which is spiritually elevating has a sense of porn in it. The
sense of a girl dancer, whether portrayed by a girl or by a man, is
perhaps, for a human being, the most luck-inducing rejuvenating
uplifting symbol that exists, in any century, in any culture -- if only
the mind is no longer condemning sexuality, no longer putting sexuality
in a category of use or misuse, of privacy or secrecy, of shame or this
or that.
Why would not the Buddha have been more outspoken on the freedom of
women and the freedom of sexuality if what I say indeed is an
enlightened, insightful thing and he indeed was enlightened? Well, I
don't know. Maybe he said it but it was disregarded as too offensive by
the established Indian culture and subconsciously filtered away in what
remains of his teachings. Maybe he was afraid that he would have been
totally disregarded if he went too far as to that delicate issue at his
time, and consciously went for a compromise. Maybe he disagreed, quite
simply. Maybe he didn't exist at all, but was invented by a set of
genius poetic masters at some time. Whatever happened, Buddha is the
only one I know of who is reputedly the founder of a world movement of
a spiritual kind who said: doubt everything! Doubt all authorities!
Doubt also the Buddha, therefore, as much as you please. Doubt
yourself, doubt your parents, doubt what you have been told over and
over again so many times you don't even know how to say the opinion
aloud, because it is simply there. It is there, as the water which you
as fish swim in. Express it. Express item by item, dig it up, get it
out, look it at, find out where your own heart and your own head is in
each little issue.
As the issues are clarified, one by one, slowly, carefully, in a
dialogical enquiring process, taking the time it must take, then more
and more you will find the myriad small light-switches in your mind
turned on. More and more, fact rather than opinion will present itself;
more and more, you will be inclined to feel that what you searched for,
has now revealed itself in a subtle way so as rather to take over your
life. Widerberg said: when that happens, don't be afraid -- just let it
take over your life.
* What is science
and why should we
bother?
It
is my sincere
opinion that we, ie humanity, are just beginners when
it comes to science. The genius of some of the proposals of Karl Popper
has not, I feel, been realized in most of what is today called
'science'. There is no intrinsic reason why an institution calling
itself 'scientific' should be anymore scientific than an institution
calling itself 'religious' should be religious, ie, delightfully
spiritual. More often than not, the dictum that 'people are the same
everywhere' -- whether they work in this or that organisation, or on
their own, 'people are people', -- is, fortunately or unfortunately,
the case.
Popper
did not
fool himself about this. He did not suggest that once we
speak the name 'science' we at once throw aside our prejudices and
start acting in a way which is profoundly rational.
What
is it to be
rational? In a footnote Popper writes that rational
thoughts are intuitions which are tested and checked; irrational
thoughts are intuitions gone wild.
Popper
urged us to
engage in a scientific discourse in which we propose
things which are refutable, somehow. Although he used Einstein's work
as an example of work that can be 'refuted' by experience it is the
case, as Arne Naess has pointed out to me, that Einstein's work contain
only tiny pieces which refer to experience whereas most of it is, as
Einstein himself described it, 'imagination' or 'fantasy' put to formal
form.
The
thrill of
looking at the concept of refutability seems to me to
convey what the standard of science is all about. If we come to know
this and learn about this and have insights about this together then we
will be able to engage as much in scientific discourse as we please,
given patience and a development of relevant skills.
What
is it to say
something refutable? It is to say something which has
a checkable, testable contact with reality. It is doubtable.
Why
is it
significant that something is refutable? Looking beyond the
original horizon of arguments which Popper provided, let us imagine a
world, vast and incomprehensible to some extent, a universe full of
complexity and also, here and there, simplicity. Indeed, we find a
universe in which the dialogue between simplicity and complexity guides
all events.
Imagine
that in
this universe there is the presence of a mind, the mind
of you yourself the scientist and you are questioning yourself about
this universe. You may propose one thing after another. Now imagine
that you propose something irrefutable.
Let
us say that
you say: Even if I can't feel it, there is, in a minute
now up-coming, a feeling inside me of happiness: and this is so even if
it is impossible to trace this feeling by any means whatsoever. How can
this be false? If there is no means of tracing this -- none,
whatsoever, for anybody, gods or us, with this or that or science
fiction technology -- then we have as good as nothing at all.
Instead
of saying
nothing at all we can say something. But to say
something we must guard what we say less, we must make it more open.
Open statements, open mind and open societies: these things go together.
When
we have a
discourse where we say things which might be checked in
a number of ways we have implicitly said things which might be refuted
in a number of ways. That is, we have said things which are (to a large
extent, or high degree) refutable. They may be true but they are
refutable; it is not to say that we refute them but they are capable of
being refuted if it so happens that they are not true. That is, there
is a contact between the statements and reality.
When
we say things
which are so packed up with conditions that it is
but a thought referring to other thoughts in a closed hierarchy or
network of thoughts then we have no ego-transcendence; we live inside a
shell; we live on prejudice and this has got nothing to do with science.
Much
of what
passes in prestigous 'scientific' institutions for
'science' may be nonscientific in this sense; and perhaps also much of
what is dismissed as 'unscientific' by such institutions may be
scientific. In an open society, we find discourses of an open kind,
involving people affirming an open mind by means of emphasizing open
statements, ie, refutable statements, and it is possible to discern
what is scientific from what is nonscientific without having to look to
the title at the person talking. It is a compassionate view, a greatly
optimistic view, and it does not matter at all that it has not been
realized: it is an obvious potential, because everyone of us, at least
as children, unless we have had disasterous childhood, has had at least
moments of excitingly honest dialogue and discourse. And if we have
this potential when we are children we have the potential no matter how
many experiences and summers we have gathered. It is there. And so, if
we bring this potential to fruition, we have a more and more open
society.
This
is an even
more lofty version of the view of the open society,
perhaps, than K. R. Popper first presented. After all, he wrote the
books as a challenge to the totalitarian regimes which were on the
raise and which led to the war during which he wrote the significant
volumes.
Popper
challenges
the way of dealing with a philosopher as a closed
package. He opens the package and looks at individual parts and modules
and asks of each to what extent it makes sense, is refutable, and, if
refutable, can be seen to survive checking with reality. He does so of
Plato and finds that the cosmology of Plato has a brilliance not at all
echoed in the racist-purist-totalitarian atttidues of Plato the
political philosopher. He praises the literary skills of Plato but
refuses to be caught in the spell of the fascist streaks of Plato. He
diagnoses Hegel and finds in Hegel's work seeds of the closed societies
that rose much later; Hegle praises irrefutable, self-enclosing,
illusion-propagating notions involving national identities and
mesmerizing people to follow a historical evolution dictated by a
system. And Popper attempts to pull out meaningful statements on
history from Marx while disclosing the irrationalities of Marx.
Had
Popper written
a third volume in the beginning of the third
millenium A.D., he might have opened the packages of the various
religious systems or teachings and similarly found that something of it
is dialogic and makes sense and is even scientifically refutable and so
possibly true and other stuff is sheer irrationality.
In
an open society
we do not say: who are we to challenge this. We
invite, openly, everyone, be it children or adults, to speak their mind
and as far as possible speak simply in ways that can be checked; and we
invite each other to point out what it is in our existing cultures,
books, and works which is of a kind that is not open-minded but which
leads to unfortunate kinds of closure.
Science
is a
standard, a standard which leads us to come to a friendly
relationship with facts. Through a friendly relationship with facts, we
can come to a friendly discourse about anything whatsoever and we let
doubt and checking by our guide, and this guide works together with the
impulse of intuition. We intuitively check that which we also say
intuitively and we invite each other to speak up if we find that we do
not do this in a way which is having this essential feature of
refutability.
In
an open
society, we must also face the question of what it means to
relate to complexities -- complexities which accumulate, perhaps, by
each decade of writing and working and sharing. It is easy for a
professor to toss away the work of a student, if the student points out
critical faults in an existing paradigm, by saying that the student
does not possibly know enough to offer a qualified kind of doubt. This
is not a scientific type of thing to say, though. It sounds nice but
there is no such thing as unqualified doubt. It is essential, for the
statements to be open, that they are available to doubt, to the mind
that can do the refuting, and this mind can be the mind of anyone who
takes a little time to look at the work.
If
you look at the
work of Albert Einstein you will see that it is not
necessary to know a great deal of mathematics nor a great deal of
physics to make sense of what he proposes and, because of that
sense-making, and because of the nature of what he says, to be able to
engage in doubt of it. It is possible, legitimate, and important: and,
as at least I think many would agree, in the specific case of
Einstein's work, also of immense significance since some of his
sentiments against quantum phenomena (transcenence of speed of light,
indeterminism) seems to be somehow unfounded.
What
I am trying
to point out is that refutability is evaded if we do
not have a fair amount of simplicity involved. If there is a great deal
of work in the aftermath of a scientific article or book, say, over
half a century or more, but a student is able to find an error in the
original piece of work which can be uttered apart from any of the
discussions in the following decades, and which is standing on its own,
then it should be judged on its own. If the student is ignorant of much
of the discussions that follows this may be in some situations an
advantage and in all cases it is scientific to consider the discourse
in its own right and not assuming that accumulated knowledge must be
sifted through.
For
just imagine
what would be the case if we would have to sift
through accumulated knowledge in an ever-progressing society each time
we were going to utter a refutable statement or a doubt of one. Then,
by each century, the amount of things to look into would have
increased, for all interesting areas in a big civilisation, beyond the
capacity of any person with a human brain and a decent life, unless
nothing else is done for years. And after several centuries, it would
take a century just to go through the accumulated knowledge unless
computers or something are used but then the criterions on which the
computers are used would have to be investigated under the same light.
Eventually, there would be no progress at all. So it is a
self-contradicting idea to assume that an ever-progressing society
involves that knowledge necessary to engage in scientific discourse is
accumulating. And it is no real answer in saying that paradigms replace
one another, and so some knowledge gets irrelevant; for if work is done
well, it transcends the notion of a paradigm and becomes part of the
accumulated amount anyhow.
So,
all in all,
scientific discourse is open and involves the genius
element of that which Karl Popper called 'refutability' if and only if
there is an essential quality of willingness to attend, to give
attention, to each question as asked entirely free from accumulated
knowledge and only refer to that which must be referred to in order to
make sense of the question and the matter it concerns. In other words,
what I am proposing is that we must be willing to accept minimalist
works, works which stand more or less on their own and which are
evaluated more or less on their own, -- and yet nevertheless we are
free, of course, to use anything accumulated if it helps in the
refutability-process connected to a scientific production or discourse.
So,
for instance,
if somebody proposes a certain type of picture of a
quantum universe with such and such characteristics it would be
interesting to look at it together with something like John von
Neumann's proof as to 'impossibility of hidden variable theories',
which made the proposals of, first, Louis de Broglie, and then David
Bohm seem irrational. However, it is possible to look into this proof,
I understand, and find that it is having a hidden assumption which
needs to be spelled out in order to really be a good proof. And this
work was done by J S Bell because he was puzzled about how Bohm could
do what von Neumann had proved impossible.
However,
if the
scientific discourse had been more scientific, so to
speak, then it would logically have been possible for the physicists at
the time of von Neumann's first proposal to discern what Bell discerned
some three decades later. This would have radically changed the
evolution of the theories of quantum physics in the twentieth century,
I believe. What happened instead was that the complexity and beauty of
von Neumann's proof led to a feeling that it was overwhelmingly
convincing. But if something is overwhelmingly convincing it is not
necessarily scientific. In fact, it is likely to be unscientific.
For
the scientific
issue is about proposing something, then letting
there be a space for doubt, a moment of silence as it were, in which
something else, something other can present itself -- perhaps a way to
refute what is said.
Now
what makes the
issues sometimes mind-tingling is that it may be
that the very process of refuting something is not itself adequately
irrefutable. And this happened to be the case, I think, when it comes
to von Neumann's work. So it is not necessarily scientific to refute
something; rather, the scientific standard is to emphasize that the
quality of the possible refusal or negation of a great deal of what is
said is present.
Let
me also point
out how important it is to realize that to engage in
such a doubt of everything at once is again unlikely to be realistic,
due to the complexity of even articulating every possible assumption
that governs this meaning-horizon in this moment without tampering with
it.
So
we are all the
time suggesting to each other what it might be
interesting to look at in the light of possible negation or possible
checking when we are doing scientific discourse of the type that Popper
suggested. And I now wish to propose, in the same light of
refutability, that this has almost never occurred in the history of
science. I admit Einstein has done something which is an exception; and
I am fully willing to admit it for elements of Niels Bohr's work and so
on. But there is not much of it.
Refutability
is,
therefore, not an absolute issue but an issue of
mind-presence. The mind-presence involving the socalled 'proof of
Fermat's second theorem' is low -- it is a professioral work involving
hefty computer programming and hundreds of pages and it is not having
the characteristic of simplicity and hence not of (a great deal of)
refutability. So, I would suggest, Fermat's theorem is still (largely)
unproved.
In
the same way, I
would suggest, the so-called string theories and so
on are not (really) theories in a scientific sense. And so I would
suggest that it is called for that we look for theories in which there
is a simplicity involving both insights from which general relativity
can be derived and insights from which quantum physics can be derived.
In this process, it is likely that some parts of each package (g.r. And
q.p.) will fall away as false or trivally meaningless when seen in new
light, while the contact-points with numerical predictions about
experience or measurements in the laboratory are likely to be upheld.
In
this book I
come with such proposals and I suggest that they have an
adequate amount of simplicity to be called refutable, and I suggest
ways in which to check these and I feel that they are true. True
statements can have the feeling of refutability: it means that they are
such that they can be negated if they have missed the point; it doesn't
mean that they have missed the point!
What
I feel is
especially interesting in the light of the standard of
refutability is that it leads to a feeling of a nonjudgemental way of
pulling out the best of the contributions from the past without
submitting to unnecessary authorities. For as Karl Popper points out
again and again, refutability is a question of relating what is said to
experience and it is not about submitting to the dogma or authority of
some tradition, genius or master in a field. Of course, when it comes
to how we speak about these things, we should also apply the same
criterion to how we relate to Popper's statements as well, and I am
sure that he would have welcomed that.
*
Can metaphysics
be refutable?
On mysticism and
rationality
Despite
whatever
political reasons there have been, or is, or will be
against metaphysics and mysticism, and despite whatever great literary
outbursts, in the language of Kant and others, there has been against
the expressions of metaphysics, we should, I feel, calmly assess
whether there is a limit to the domain of statements which can be
refutable and, in the popperian sense, rational.
I
am now
endavouring to do with Karl Popper as he has deftly done with
so many in his writings: to take somethin and discard something else.
For I haven't got the sense that Popper got it all right when he used
his refutability insight in the area of metaphysics. I am granting
Popper, by virtue of my own intuition and also experience, full rights
in asserting that refutability is essential to any scientific
statement. I see that Popper joins the club of the anti-metaphysicists
in some of his writings, also in The Open Society, although with not a
great deal of comments. I feel that he has got it wrong there. But I
also know that in great many circles which proclaim their interest in
being scientific and rationally oriented, there is a similar sentiment
against the mysticist and the metaphysical. So I will venture into
these questions with respect and do so calmly and simply and as honest
as I am able to, from one thought to the next.
In
order to come
into resonance or contact with the kind of
anti-metaphysical sentiment that Popper and many others echo, I will
first say something as to how I agree to some of it. For instance, Kant
doubts that there is such a thing as progression in the field of
metaphysics; because he does not see that adding something to something
which is already in contradiction with itself can help solving it. (By
the way, all my references to Popper's views and to related
philosophers are through the two Open Society volumes unless
specifically mentioned. In this age of computerized searching I have
not, in the first edition at least, bothered to note page number and so
on and so forth for each of these comments and, as that would have
added to the refutability of my references, I should have; and I
apologize that I don't do it but I can assure that if we get into a
territory with little-known information I will give full checkable
references there.)
Of
course,
metaphysical works aiming to prove things which are laid out
in such propaganda documents as bibles and such -- proving by means of
chatting and more chatting -- are not trustworthy examples of
scientific discourse, generally speaking. That is to me a trivial
point.
If
something
starts off wrong, with contradictions or with quotations
of socalled prophets, whatever they are called, holy so-and-so, peace
be with him, and all that nonsense, -- then it is unlikely that adding
a little more clarification to some of the concepts can be subsumed
under the general heading of 'progress' with much justification.
All
this is to
anyone who is in favour of such things as doubt,
clarity, dialogue, honesty and so on obvious, clear, trivial, easy -- I
would say. Perhaps that is a too strong statement but I do not intend
to elaborate on the need not to be gullible here because I have
elaborated much on that need, also in the form of written dialogue, in
earlier manuscripts (see yoga4d.com/dialudes.htm).
What
is abundantly
clear to me is that it is a big leap from this to
asserting of all metaphysics that it is irrational or of all mysticism
that it is incapable of the kind of refutable statements which we have
already discussed. It is a big leap and it may be right but it may also
be wrong and it is no argument that we or you or me are not interested
in metaphysics or mysticism so it is no issue anyway. Is it or is it
not the case that metaphysics and mysticism can have statements of the
refutable kind?
The
question seems
simple but of course we must look a little into what
we mean by the words to get a clearer question, which has an even
simpler reference.
By
my 'motto' of
'passion without greed or hatred' I mean a passion
also to explore and enquire which has a great deal of patience in it,
allowing for alternate perspectives to come in and have their say,
before we progress. Let us have this wind of free play of dialogue and
say something general about metaphysics and mysticism before we go on.
I am willing to look for meanings now of both terms which does not have
to give any credit to parroting of socalled 'spiritual authorities'.
The
word
'metaphysics' in its roots seems to refer to reality, or
nature, physics as 'what is born', what comes naturally, but with the
word 'meta' meaning something like above or after. That is, there is
something relaxed, detached, even, about metaphysics. Perhaps the
metaphor of trees versus forest can do: one speaks of the importance of
seeing the forest, not just the trees. That is, whereas physics may be
said to deal with the trees, metaphysics is also about the forest.
Metaphysics,
then,
tends to take questions as to the whole very
seriously. Now Popper has a bias which he shares with Einstein in
denying the validity of anything which is not local as something more
than a mere thought or fancy of the 'collective'. So to Popper -- and
this is of course a political view as well -- the individual matters in
a sense which is almost absolute and that explains why it is so
important for Popper to speak of the open society in which each
individual can have his or her free say -- and I am all for that. But I
dare say: is it a refutable statement -- and if so, is it true -- that
the collective is an illusion?
How
can we check
whether the notion of the collective is an illusion or
whether it refers to reality? Well, we could look into something like
physics and ask whether there is any evidence that groupings of large
processes might have something physically directly and immediately in
common. Alas, from Popper's perspective, there are indications of this
-- but not in Einstein's relativity theories. In quantum theory,
although in an implicit way (usually, but we will look into a fresh way
which we will describe here for the first time), energy processes can
and do have features in common over great distances given certain
extremely general conditions which we cannot rule out that apply given
the present state of physics. So I am willing to say that the notion
that the collective is an illusion is a refutable statement and that it
is also false, and that, hence, Popper is wrong if he asserts this.
Mysticism,
unlike
metaphysics, does not contain a direct reference to
reality (such as its root 'physics'), but rather refer more to the
subject, the perceiver, who is supposed to be able to relate to the
whole existence beyond the sensory organs, also with closed eyes. But
why not? It is a statement which, given some elaboration, can be given
a refutable form: a person can relate to facts in other ways than by
means of sensory organs. We can then proceed to check this and if we
look at attempts on extra-sensory perception we find not very
convincing evidence, as far as I am aware of, now referring to
twentieth-century literature on this in science. However, I have a
great deal of personal experience that I know can be translated into
types of experiments which has not been performed in the most
talked-about ESP experiments. For instance, I would say that it is of
great importance to entrain resonance between the whole nervous system
and not just the brain of at least two persons for a long time, like
three months, in order to establish the grounds for pervasive
telepathy. Now if you don't believe in such I am granting you that
right, of course, but please see that what I just offered is within the
realm of the refutable and so it is not a statement that lacks an
intended touch with reality. It may be wrong but I think it is right.
And if we are both interested and have time we might even find out a
great deal about it, check it and see if it can stand the checks. I
think it can.
I
also think that
humanity is, as I said in the beginning, hardly into
puberty yet as far as scientific thinking goes and is it one thing that
science has only grudglingly accepted then it is anything involving
immediacy and direct contact. Science, at least before Popper, seemed
to a large extent to be founded on the idea of the local. The
nonlocality of quantum physics crept into it only as a result of
Einstein's repeated claim, to Bohr, that physics should be local: it
resulted in a proposal that such a restriction was unnecessarily narrow
from the group around Bohr. Eventually the concept of 'nonlocality'
came out of this. Confer the socalled EPR article of (I think) 1935,
where Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen proposes the locality criterion in a
critique of the form that quantum theory had got through the work of
Bohr's group in Copenhagen (the socalled Copenhagen Interpretation).
Many
years later,
what J S Bell did in the mid 1960s, and what Alain
Aspect then did empirically in 1980, the concept of nonlocality came
into physics in a way that was rational, strong and (as far as we can
see now) unavoidable.
The
grounding of
elementary physics on nonlocality does not
automatically mean that it applies, at ordinary human temperatures, for
something like our nervous systems. However it is at least a clear
conceptual rational theoretical foundation which entirely surpasses the
old idea (among some socalled mysticists) that ESP had to do with plain
radio waves. Here we are talking of something prior to electromagnetic
waves; we are talking of the very probability wave patterns which lay
out the likely pattern for energy to follow -- that these probabilities
may interact, so to speak, with each other even though they refer to
energies widely apart. In sum, there is a connection-across-distance
and this is something that Einstein quite simply found untastely (he
spoke of it as 'ghostly' in his Ideas and Opinions).
However,
when
someone speaks of science and of physics as if it is
obvious to any rational person that mysticism is irrational I feel that
the person is not only wrong, but dangerously close to irrationalism
himself. For once we begin to look at what mysticism means we find that
it is a lot of refutable statements we can enter into and it is by no
means obvious to all who are learned about physics at least to some
extent that this is all wrong. So when somebody dismisses mysticism or
metaphysics without argument, I would say that is untastely and
whatever we can say of Einstein, his way of doing things involved a
sense of the openly expressed; he did not conceal and he did not toss
things away without giving a reason that was either profoundly
subjective (such as when he spoke of something as 'ghostly') or which
was rational. Einstein related his ideas and opinions under the heading
'Ideas and Opinions' and this is an eminent example of his good taste.
He did not speak of his bias as the final truth but elucidated exactly
what he meant and offered it.
So
while I
disagree with Einstein's dismissal of the nonlocal it is
clear that what he said helped the dialogue immensely in many ways, the
dialogue that led to more and more and more of physics. At the same
time, if we apply some of his criterions of beauty and simplicity to
the present state of physics, I think he would have said that not much
has happened. My late friend David Bohm indeed said the same (and he
happened to work with Einstein some weeks before launching his
controversional career).
I
have had the the
chance of discussing the issues of metaphysics and
mysticism with strongly pro-Kant thinkers of some sharp logical
training. While they started out with an outright dismissal, generally
speaking, of such things as metaphysics, the result, after some
sessions of conversation, was usually that they no longer regarded it
as impossible that mysticiam and metaphysics can have a rational and
even scientific foundation. I am not sure that we really reached
agreement or that we achieved a sense of feeling the same amount of
interest in the positive possibility of these things. However it is
clear that there was a movement from deeming the whole idea as
inherently irrational to deeming it possible and clearly within the
domain of the rationally discussable. (In order to make this statement
a little more checkable I will, in this case, mention one person with
whom I had such a series of conversations some time ago, to which this
general statement can be seen to apply, and that was with the grand-son
of Arne Naess, Tore Naess, himself educated in philosophy and
mathematical logic.)
But
instead of
adding opinions in favour of mysticism and metaphysics I
wish to go back to the original question, having now the background of
this discussion warm in our minds, perhaps: can a metaphysical
statement be refutable? Can a mystical statement, or statements
regarding a mystical approach to life, be refutable?
Trusting
the
process of negation, as J. Krishnamurti called, I wish to
phrase the statement which I most feel is in odds with the truth, with
a question-mark. This something I have experienced as clarifying time
and again in various dialogues in all areas of life and thinking. In
this case I can say:
Does
it make sense
to say that all statements relating to reality as a
whole are irrefutable?
Are
all statements
referring to wholeness irrefutable?
Are
all statements
referring to the wholeness of existence beyond any
question of checking?
What
leaps to my
mind in this moment as I just wrote the question in
that way is to ask: what do we mean by checking, in the most general
case?
The
answer of the
circle around Rudolf Carnap, sometimes called 'the
logical positivists' or 'the logical empiricists', is that checking
means looking to sensory data and comparing our statements with them. A
statement which does not have any such correspondence, whether
affirming or disconfirming, is 'metaphysical' and, as far as science
goes, something which should be ruled out -- they said. As far as I
have heard.
If
my metaphysics
is that of extreme and absolute locality then Carnap
had it right. But only because that metaphysics is right. And if that
metaphysics is not accepted, then we cannot accept the dictum that
measurement data can only concern the local and not the whole of the
universe. To give an example of the extreme alternative, I know of (and
have talked with, in depth, about the issue) a professor of physics
named Holger Bech Nielsen (at Copenhagen Bohr Institute) who suggests
that if in the future the universe should perish it should have certain
observable consequences concerning some particle properties in the here
and now due to a feedback in the time dimension. That is most probably
beyond what most would consider 'ordinary physics' and me, for one,
thinks that some of the assumptions in the reasoning are just faulty
(the determinism for one). But I am willing to look into the argument
and Nielsen is one of the founders of elements of the string theory and
certainly a mind of great standing in physics. He speaks of
measurements which involve a property of the entire universe, albeit in
the future.
What
seems to me
to pervade Kant's writings and to me make most of them
utterly boring to read is a fragmented view of the human being as a
lone island, disconnected entirely. It is a metaphysical viewpoint that
Kant has, as far as I can see, and that is of the individual as having
a mind that is beyond the rest of the world. I think Kant is, indeed,
projecting an implicit metaphysics here and so I think he is in
self-contradiction in trying to toss away all of metaphysics if that is
indeed what he is trying. And I feel that the same argument goes
against Carnap and his circle in early Vienna. As far as I can tell,
both Bertrand Russell and Karl Popper suffers of the virus of not
seeing that localism (as we can call it -- the idea that the
local is necessarily more real in its disconnection from the rest of
reality and in particular the mind of the thinker as an island apart
from everything else) is indeed a form of metaphysics.
And
I am willing
to go as far as to say that it is indeed this
particular metaphysics defending itself preconsciously that lead to
the empiricist attitude of 'tossing away metaphysics and mystical
statements'. It is not a tossing away of all metaphysics, only of that
which is not the one chosen.
I
would say, then,
that it is brought forward in a logical way here
that there is no a priori reason to judge metaphysics as beyond the
domain of the refutable. There is no a priori reason to judge sensory
organs as beyond metaphysics. A mystical statement may possibly be
refutable and there is no faulty logic when one admits this possibility
but rather it is a subtle error to not see that logical empiricism is
tainted by a localist metaphysics and a localist mysticism. This is
shared with the personal philosophy of Albert Einstein but Einstein
expressed his views, as far as I can tell, rather fully and expertly so
that they can be doubted; whereas I am not sure that most other
criticers of the not local or metaphysical have expressed their views
so well (and hence, so refutable).
*
Modes of
Questioning
With
the belief
that Karl Popper has in what he calls intuition or
intellectual intuition -- an intuition which he has a faith in which is
qualified by the condition that he regards intuitions as something
which ought to be checked, because it is fallible -- we can ask any
question whatsoever and intuit answers, and proceed to check them
insofar as we have made our answers checkable or refutable.
Let
us notice how
much more subtle this attitude to the activity of the
scientist is than the vulgar 'pulp art' version of Popper's view of
science. Popper is a person who has a solid belief in intuition and so
cannot be classed together in a tight way with the rigid narrow-minded
kind of empiricism. However, as I pointed out in last chapter, I do not
consider that he has properly used his intuition and his logical skills
on making explicit the consequence of this, namely that the denial of
the refutability of metaphysical claims is itself a metaphysically
based claim and so a contradiction.
In
this chapter I
will propose four modes of questioning.
1
-- acquiring mode
2 -- destilling
mode
3 -- refuting mode
4 -- infinity mode
In
the acquiring
mode, we do such trivial things -- typically of the
bad kind of school teacher or university lecturer -- as to instill an
attitude that the question is about accumulating knowledge-stuff. This
accumulation can be of word definitions, translations, grammar rules,
pieces and bits of knowledge of various second-hand kind, quotes, and
so on. I regard the whole thing trivial to the extent it is boring and
yet it seems there are philosophers who have given years and years to
elucidating the nuances of questions and answers in the acquiring mode
as if it were some kind of godhood or fountainhead and it is exactly
for that reason I feel it is called for to give this type of
questioning a name.
So
as to warn of
this mode: for it tends to clutter the mind, it is
about accumulation, and an accumulation that may make less and less
room for insight. For it quenches innocence by experience, unless
tempered by the other three.
*
In the second
mode, which I prefer to call the destilling mode, or the
mode of destilation, the aim of the question is to throw away
accumulated noise and elucidate how something is false so as to reach a
point of contact with a truth in the matter. This is evidently the
negation concept of J. Krishnamurti. He was a master in its practise
and it can be frightening before one tries it oneself, and learn to
relish it as a fine wine. But it is more than a wine, it is a
necessity. The question asked is, without making it into a formula,
typically the statement of what you suspect is wrong with a
question-mark after. When this question is asked, you may feel that
instead of acheiving greater clarity, there is a set of opinions
involved in the question which is in fact asserted in the act of asking
the question.
When
a question
thus conceals the mere affirmation of prejudice, it is
proper, in the destilling mode, to suggest that the question may be
wrong or we may need to go deeper and look at the issue in a way which
is more direct.
In
going deeper,
we can achieve yet another question which is such that
when it is asked, something falls away as obviously not the point of
progress in the issue, and this leaves a space in the mind for an
actual intuition or immediate insight or what Karl R Popper calls an
intellectual insight.
*
In the refuting
mode, we are stating a research question with an
empirical angle so as to check against reality. This is a question with
regard to experience, perhaps -- as I would like to point out,
following the enquiry in the former chapter -- an experience involving
something beyond mere local issues. It can be an enquiry into
wholeness, felt and experienced directly, for instance. It can also be
an enquiry into the quantum phenomena beyond any quantum tradition. It
is the point of touch for a theory with experience, and it involves
statements which in Popper's terms are refutable. This may, then, also
be called the refutability mode.
*
In the infinity
mode, which is related to the destilling mode but which
is beyond concern with any particular issue or with reaching any
particular insight, the act of questioning is so as to guide the mind
to come to a sense of infiniteness.
When
William Blake
or Walt Whitman asks their questions in their poems,
whether using question-mark or indicating their wonder in some other
way, they are sometimes, I feel, touching on an infinity mode. The
question mode is not merely acquiring or destilling, nor strictly
refuting, it is a questioning mode apt to induce a meditative state, a
trance, it does the job of a drug only it does it better for it leaves
no residue of chemical poison which must be cleared away afterwards.
The
infinity mode
is getting high without a hangover, it is the act of
asking things like, 'What is "what is"?' and staying with the emptiness
and the fullness of not knowing and yet knowing in that
not-knowingness. These are not issues of conventional paradox but they
may involve a sense of positive contradiction. When analyzed in one of
the other questioning modes, in particular the first or third, they may
seem like nonsense and it is this nonsensical aspect that has led, I
feel, to much of the condemnation of the mystical approach among many
of the early logicians. However, one must be willing to say that it
seems strange to suggest that the feelings involved in poems like
Leaves of Grass, and the statements that surrounds them, are mere
tokens of confusion. Certainly it may be a token of confusion to
disregard such a work of art.
And
it is exactly
in the fourth mode of questioning that we can
naturally, more naturally than in any of the earlier three, bring in
the concept of art. Art as the creative spirit, playful and ever
humorous, bringing new senses of synchronistic experience to the mind
that is not clinging to the ego and selfishness of logicism of the
petty sensory-bound kind. And yet the fourth mode can convey itself
through questions that refer also to the senses, and so the mysticist
can open her eyes to the leaves of grass and find also there the
implicate order of the whole universe, with luck and grace.
In
the fourth mode
we can also touch on tantric feelings of orgasm and
delight and in my phrase 'resonating over dancers' I am personally
giving an impression of what it is to meet a freshly educated ballet
girl also in bed, and in her naked unselfish improvised dance at a
floor -- and in meeting her gaze, seeing everything in that
nothingness. Formulating these things may lead to the poetic style of
open-ended questions which has a tone of the ambigious or infinite or
complementary in it.
I
would also say
that any great act of a scientific character involves
a suspension of assumptions criss-crossing all four modes of
questioning and possibly any other modes as well. David Bohm, in the
last conversation I had with him, that time over phone, spoke of the
difficulty in suspending assumptions, suspending somehow also emotions
-- is it possible, he asked, to suspend a feeling, to let a feeling and
not just its intellectual content be up for attentive questioning gaze?
For then dialogue begins and its narrow purposes fall away, he
suggested. And indeed this was a recurrent theme some of the times I
spoke with him. Too sad he couldn't live longer to work further on
these issues which to him was also an expression of decades of
experience of way too little dialogue in his own field of expertise,
something which is documented fairly well in various books.
Then
again, if we,
like Bohm, speak of 'suspending assumptions' we must
take care not to try too much at once so as to achieve nothing at all
in the area of questioning. If we lump together the negation of
Krishnamurti with the refutability of Popper and simultaneously want a
kick of wholeness it may be little of each in practise. That is why I
have not included 'suspending assumptions' in any of the categories but
rather regard it as a (perhaps positively) blurred expression which can
relate to them all, because any such division of mental phenomena is
bound to be surpassed, on occasions, no matter how accurate it may be,
by situations in which they all act as one.
One
more word on
the infinity mode: I am of the opinion that
mathematics is less the issue of clear-cut proof than I thought it
were. After spending many nights and long weeks and then months and
doing so regularly with Goedel's proof and corrolaries I have
re-iterated again and again certain definitions which I now later have
come to see as unclear ideas. No matter how much we do computer
simulation and checking of the rules we employ in our socalled 'proofs'
it remains to see whether a proof stand. I go further than Popper, I
think, in my willingness to apply the refutability type of criterion
also to mathematics (for he seems to make an exception for mathematical
proofs). It is never certain that a proof is a proof -- that is a motto
I have learned to come to as a truth. It is, and it must be treated as
such, a refutable statement that something is a proof.
In
the middle of
this book, or thereabouts, we will return to some
surprising mathematical issues.
Let
me also add
that it would be presumptious to claim that I have
successfully carried out the refutability mode in all these essays and
musings. In particular, I have used something like the destilling mode
(I hope, at least), in the essays on spiritual feeling. Yet also in
them the refutability mode or the refuting mode remains an aspiration
and a quiet measuring rod.
*
Youthfulness
and the theory of
happiness
Let
us most
playfully -- in this section -- apply some of the calm
insight-tools on an area of concern for us all: the theory, or at least
the assumptions we have surrounding the all-important area of happiness
or life joy. If it is possible to come to some kind of communion in
understanding as to the deepest quest of us all -- the end beyond all
ends, the aim higher than all aims -- then it is also possible to say:
if we have, at a human level, in society some kind of conflict but we
know this aim beyond aim in togetherness, then it is of means we are in
conflict and this is not such a tragedy, surely we can work this out.
So
the basis for
peace may be to suspend our immediate concerns and
meet, face to face, in an open enquiry which is regularly renewed, I
suppose -- given a new vocabulary and so on -- as to the nature of
happiness itself. And there is no garantee that there will be
agreement, of course. Also we must learn something of what it means to
enquire so that we do not come to such a meeting merely with the
intention to propagandize a solution which we do not intend to doubt or
submit to modes of questioning such as to destill an essence or provide
testable claims, claims which each can test in his or her experience.
I
feel that
happiness is intrinsically concerned with some sort of
progress, in the sense of the fresh growth of new flowers and fruits
all the time, the youthfulness of looking ahead and feeling that there
is a movement in conjoinance with that looking. It is when progression
feels good that the enjoyment of the movement in itself is greatest, I
propose. And every moment of great absorption has something new,
unparroted, creative in it, and as such provides a datum to the future
in the sense of insight, new avenues of exploration, new possibilities.
This is the quintessence of youthfulness and I feel it is of utmost
importance that we realize that progress does not merely have to do
with this or that societal factor or with silly goals.
Progress
as a
sense of life unfolding, life being taken care of, is
itself joy, and it is something other than the crumpling of things
which no longer upheld themselves. In the entropy of dead matter there
is but the gravitation of going toward the center, falling apart in
pieces, disintegrating. The impulse of life as it exists in coherence,
rather, with everything else that is living, more or less (less in the
case of a hungry lion or puma seeing a zebra or canine, yet in many
cases the situation is that of kinship even between, say, birds of very
different sizes and shapes in meeting a common source of food and
water). This impulse of life works to bring matter in circulation in a
way that is characterized by a harmony which in the old ages would have
been called a 'divine' harmony. And I would say, why not? Why can we
not say divine harmony? For surely we have not depicted on paper in the
form of rules the essence of the harmony of life, the feelings that
pervade plays of Bach or Beethoven and which makes the brain sounder
and the skin more resillient when we allow the music to fill our
working surroundings.
I
hear that
scientists have shown that some pieces of Mozart tend to
evoke more expertise of a mathematical kind in schoolchildren and I am
not surprised at all, if it is correct.
So
we have a
bundle of words, progress, health, harmony, happiness,
learning, insight, meditation, and the act of being creative. These
words belong together with youthfulness, with going ahead.
Youthfulness, I suggest, is the aptitude of life to relate to future as
if it were real, in some open and exciting way, whether we are five or
fifty or of a completely different age.
Youthfulness
is
something we can anchor ourselves in by renewing our
contact with all the highest feelings and types of actions which evokes
those higher feelings. Generosity is also a key point here; just as a
fruit tree is yielding of fruits which must be plucked or else they may
deteroriate and bring problems to the tree, so is the youthful person
overflowing with skillfully readied products or processes which are not
patented and put aside in a box but given. This action of giving allows
the capacity to give well and give much to grow. So generosity calls on
the means to be generous in the future.
I
will have more
to say about these issues in a later chapter on ethics
and worldviews etc.
*
Paul Feyerabend
on Popper
Paul
Feyerabend
has given some worthwhile impulses, in such books as
"Against Method", published in the U.S. in the 1970s, to correct
certain aspects of Popper's proposals.
For
instance,
Feyerabend strongly argues against the use of the notion
of method in the idea of the essential scientific practise. He
emphasises that it goes beyond rules (and is in this sense
"anarchistic") and that much of the best of recorded discoveries in
science comes from hunches, guesswork, intuitions, and indeed also a
focus on contradictions, on bringing up counter-factual issues, of
pushing through seemingly irrational beliefs and so on and so forth.
However,
as far as
I can tell, Feyerabend lashes out too strongly. His
focus on Chaos is worthwhile only as a correction to an emphasis on the
intent to relate to reality, otherwise it declines, just as Nietzsche's
philosophy, into the 'harsh anarchism' (that I have sought to avoid in
my emphasis on 'compassionate anarchism', see
www.yoga4d.com/dialudes.htm).
Consistent
with
Feyerabend's insistence on the irrational, Feyerabend
critisizes the very thought that there can be such a thing as a fact in
a sense which is independent of ideology.
Let
me say
something about the issue of fact first. We may intend a
factual statement but be uncertain as to whether we have got one. We
may be humble with regard to reality without saying that it is
impossible to have contact points with reality in our thoughts and in
our expressions. We may rightly suspect or engage in doubt as to
whether we have let ideology bias how we relate to reality, so that
what appears to be independent fact is in fact a mixture of fact and
ideological or emotional bias. But all of this is consistent with the
opinion that there may be such a thing as a fact in an independent
sense, independent from both method and ideology, from attachment of an
emotional kind and from fears and so on.
My
sense of a fact
is that it involves a bonding or a resonance between
our attention and reality through a thought-form of some kind,
involving also a feeling. This is a feeling involving a relationship
beyond attachment. Attachment is a resistance to let go of a particular
attitude and leads to both suffering and illusion; when I speak of a
passion beyond greed I also mean a passion which is a bonding and a
love beyond attachment. This is a subtle issue and a tranquility or
harmonious excitation of mind which is a result of insight and a
relationship to fact. It comes through intending a factual contact not
by dismissing the idea that there is anything but ideological stories
perturbed by some kind of obscure world. This intent involves dialogue,
a stretching towards something greater than our own thought. This I see
as a scientific standard, but I agree with Feyerabend that it is not
about method. In this Feyerabend also agrees with J. Krishnamurti, who
is well-known for his insistence that holism must not be bound in
method, technique or following of a path.
What
do I mean by
speaking of a scientific standard rather than a
scientific method? I speak of an intent of intelligence, the
intelligence that reads between the lines as a result of a relationship
characterized by affinity, affection, interest, enthusiasm and wonder.
So
we can call
this, in short, for a methodless standard of science.
The
methodless
standard of science proceeds by simple, interesting
statements of a refutable quality for which we gather instances of
confirmation and which we are ready to let go of on encountering
instances of disconfirmation. (The phrase 'instance of
disconfirmation' I have got from Arne Naess). In the interest of
fact, we are actively pursuing also instances of disconfirmation. As a
very simple example, a computer programmer does not only test the
program with examples that does not challenge the program structure. He
or she is willing to face the situation that program breaks down under
pressure because this is an instance of disconfirmation that can lead
to further work on the program, so as to make an excellent program. A
discovery that the program does not work is a positive discovery. So
the program is considered refutable and creative work sets in -- not as
a method, except in unusual cases, but rather as an inventive art -- to
challenge the program. This leads to facts about the program. If the
programmer is open-minded and willing to relate to fact then fruitful
insights are generated and more interesting programs are made as a
result thereof. This is a progress akin to the general progress we can
see in science i it has a similar scientific standard. So the standard
is methodless, or not dependent on method.
Refutability,
then, is not, as Feyerabend seems to think, a question
merely of method. It is beyond method a question of quality. The
refutability quality pertains to a question or a statement about
reality. It is a quality or ingredient of humility and openness (or
what D.Bohm called 'vulnerability').
So,
I think it is
fair to say that Feyerabend does not criticize as
much Popper's ideas as he critizes his own ideas of what Popper said.
For Popper is fully agreeing and aware of the role of intuition and the
irrational in all scientific work and even defines rationality as
intuitions checked in contrast to intuitions gone wild. The 'gone wild'
feature of the destructive types of chaos (such as when corruption sets
in) can hardly be what Feyerabend would call good science. So I fear
that Feyerabend is putting the case way too strong. It makes sense only
as a voice among several voices in the dialogue as to what science is;
but if Feyerabend became the law then science would cease to be
anything but propaganda, quarreling without standards, and look like an
advertising business which portrays all sorts of nonexisting vitamins
in their glossy schampoo ads. To actually relate to fact some essential
reverence towards fact need to be intended and cultivated and while we
can agree that this is not about method it is about something else than
'anything goes'. It is about selecting something rather than everything
on the ground of good taste. And good taste in science is about the
quality of refutability.
On
issues of
logic, Feyerabend suggests that much of science proceeds
by contradictions rather than by actions to rule them out. I will
return to this point. I agree, on the level of attitude, that way too
much hope has been invested in ruleboundedness and consistency issues
not just for decades, but for centuries in science, and I feel that
experience with computer programming is apt to help a person to get
insight into the role of rules and the essential notion of a 'law',
also so as to get beyond rules and notions of this kind. I feel that
mathematics, as discipline, is still wrought with a self-glorification
as to its own handling of this type of issues, and I will return to
some essential mathematical questions shortly.
*
Ethics and
worldviews
In
a situation of
abundance, where challenges are few, and problems
small enough to be solved by any of a dozen available effortless
nonviolent means, even without a great deal of attention to them,
ethics can be largely a set of rules, a code, taught in schools, which
is expected to be graciously followed by most. However, reality may be
radically different.
Where
resources
are scarce, where people have gathered -- and maintain
-- power in unfair ways, where threats of violence and violence itself
has got some kind of upper hand and humanity has no longer got the
upper hand, ethics can say whatever it wants but things may be tough to
change in praxis.
A
child growing up
on fairytales and glossy movies in a relatively
peaceful corner of an otherwise pretty barbaric society may too late
realize that a great deal of what happens is not at all based on what
his or her mother and father taught. The mechanisms of the world may be
the greed for power and prestige which leads to much cunning,
corruption and treatment of other people as if they were merely means.
Indeed,
anybody
who is absolutely certain as to what is merely 'means'
may be infected with a point of view that leads to ruthless pursuit of
goals; his or her code of honor may be connected to superficial matters
such as prestige and there is no room in this for the whispers of the
heart and conscience.
When,
in such a
bleak situation, which also concern computer
programmers, but is not limited to any particular type of activity, it
seems -- somebody asks: are you ethical? Are your actions based on
ethics? Then what do you answer? Do you face the question honestly,
feel it over, relate to the question? And, if it so happens that the
answer is not a clear yes, then what is it that makes you act against
your heart? Do you follow? Without asking these questions there may be
very little inward happiness.
Somebody
may ask:
What is the point of being ethical, in a world which
is corrupt? But then the age-old saying still holds: Be in the world,
without being of it. Be in the world, but don't be made of it. Don't
ground your life in the actions of the corrupt.
Then
again, why
not? What is the validity of being ethical? And how do
we really judge whether an action is ethical or not, whole or not,
righteous or not?
Should
we look to
a book? Obviously not. Looking to a book is merely a
repetition of a certain attitude and ethics concerns real life, real
relationship, actual people and no book of a finite number of pages can
answer to the infinity of life.
So
we must look
inside our own heart. Then why should we listen to it?
There
is perhaps
no 'should'. But let us see what happens if we listen
to our hearts, if we insist on asking a question again and again until
we become silent (cfr the chapter on 'modes of questioning', the
destilling mode etc).
Instead
of merely
asserting in an irrefutable way that we are
incorrupt, let us say things in a refutable way, enabling a science
sense about our own psyche.
And
in what
worldview does our actions take place? I mean, what is the
world, seen in terms of actions and their effects, relationship and so
on?
What
happens with
the body, the mind, the feelings, the quantity of
luck, the amount of rejuvenation and beauty, the ability to understand
things with intelligence if we do not act righteously? You follow?
Somebody
who
engages in threats, for instance, to get his or her own
way around, is engaging in tacit violence. So that person is not a
passifist. There is an old saying about letting God judge and deliver
the punishment. Why should we not ourselves deliver punishments? We
need to ask these questions, so as to evoke our intelligence. If we
merely assume that everybody except some 'elements' act righteously, we
are not relating to what state humanity is in, and has been in for
thousand of years. Let us face it, we are barbarians, and the societies
we create are not really civilized in any high sense. When we start
imposing things on each other by means of violence we are enforcing our
stupidity. Do we see that? These things are too important to be left
out from any book discussing wholeness, the universe, and so on. Do you
see that the worldview you have is intrinsically related to how you
justify your own actions?
If
you act without
the full support of your heart in any area
whatsoever, if you engage in violence or threats, in cunning or
corruption, if you set prestige above the quest for enlightenment for
all, then you have no luck, your body gets ugly, you stumble in your
own feet, the things you try to achieve will stink, and the really good
powers will be out of reach for you. Instantly. Do you see why? In a
world in which subtle energies, mind-energies, swirl around and create
subtle feelings, the whispers of our hearts, then life is about being
obedient to that and trusting it, trusting the intelligence of love, of
compassion. Does this love ever make threats as to the use of violence?
So
there is an
infinity given to you when you act based on the whispers
of your heart, when you are quiet, question your prejudices, cleanse
your mind, ground yourself in a full conscience where you love life,
love the rejuvenating life of integrity, love that state of being
innocent and not corrupt. Otherwise there will be just sadness and even
the beauty of a sunset will fail to impress you. Please, I am not
patronizing, I merely strongly hope that we can engage in enquiry, each
on our own, and also together, and listen and relate to the
implications of these enquiries. We must not loose our hearts, but stay
tuned to them, to the love of individuals, to the joy of being
sensitive in relationship yet strong in our own feelings of compassion.
Then luck and rejuvenation and success and so on can come but it will
not taint our hearts. This is the basis, I feel, for formulating
adequate worldviews. Worldviews in which wholeness gets a primary role,
in which we see that life is somehow infinite and that we will somehow
all be around always in some sense so as to face the consequences of
all our actions unless we purify ourselves, transform ourselves
completely now.
For
the past can
be dissolved, can it not? We do not have to portray
our life as somehow taking place "in the middle" between a past and a
future, a past full of misguided actions that we must justify and a
future which is merely a modification of that past. No, in seeing the
absurdity of our own past, not judging, but just seeing how rediculous
it is, with a flash of shame but going beyond also shame, we can toss
it away. The past does not have to be there. We can pick that which has
wholeness in it, care for that of the past which shines with a light of
integrity. But all our troubles can dissolve in a worldview in which a
primary role is given to the future and to the present moment as
somehow enrolled in that future and vice versa.
*
The role of the
body in
painting
For
as long as the
digital machine was in the future, rather than the
present, in civilisation, there were tendencies in all areas of human
activity to seek to exemplify the digital. This particular seeking took
the form, as for the visual arts, of looking toward the mechanical and
sharply symmetrical and away from the body, the organic and Nature. So
it is perhaps not so strange that there has been decades at the closing
of the twentieth century in which, in many or most major art schools,
the body was only 'allowed' to be shown if it were in a context of
something sufficiently technological, like in the context of
photography.
But
in
contemporary art, when the organic were shown through such
technological forums as photography, even then we saw that such things
as mechanical repetition of the same motive, or other mechanical
manipulations, would have to 'justify' the inclusion of something
organic. So it would not appear archaic and thus contrary to the (lost)
spirit of contemporary art.
Fortunately,
due
to the density of digital technology, there has been
for a while a revision of the prejudice against the organic and the
analogue. What may surface in the present Large Discourse on Art may be
something along the lines which I will suggest in the following. I
mention this also to warn the reader that I am now presenting views
which in many influential circles may be seen as controversial, to say
the least.
First
of all, I
welcome the introduction of digital technology to human
consciousness and think of it as a new way in which creativity can be
expressed -- cheaply, yet with depth; with immense possibilities of
reproduction, even over vast distances -- which one day will be steller
distances -- and also as contrast to the analogue.
Thanks
to the
digital it is possible to sharpen the intuitive
understanding of the analogue and see the analogue as the bearer of the
digital, rather as an ocean as a whole is the bearer of the individual
waves which showers in over a beach, -- a world which is whole and in
which the digital is but a small part.
Thanks
to the
digital technology what was once thought of as some kind
of mysterious mathematical order can now be seen as merely a bag of
tricks. There is, in a way, no ultimate mathematics but only a question
of a selection of route procedures. And none of these route procedures
can be adequate to account for the fullness of life.
The
fullness of
life derives from, and expects, a fundamentally
anarchist view of sexuality, as an orgie of beauty, joy and creativity
which can be an offspring of goodness and the fullness of intelligence
for a living organism. In few mammals born of Earth do we find such an
intensity of natural inborn sexuality as in the adult human being. One
of the things that distinguishes human beings from most types of apes
and chimpanzees is that human beings are prepared to copulate almost
all the time. Take this together with the fact of the natural sense of
openness and vulnerability that the human skin suggests, as compared
the skin of a very hairy mammal, and we see a situation in which the
sensitivity of the sensual is actively invited by virtue of the
inherent 'design' of the human body.
The
human body,
furthermore, is propelled by a brain which is activated
to a large extent through feeling of which sexual feeling involves a
great deal of these feelings, at least potentially.
The
fall of the
human being into the abyss of condemnation of the
sexual, together with the condemnation of half of humanity -- the
female part -- is to a large part responsible of the division between
art and pornography. I would say that it is impossible to be a truly
good, creative, happy, and inspiring artist, representing life, unless
there is a solid grounding in pornography.
Let
me draw a line
between violence and all sorts of sexuality. For any
social anthropologist knows that there are well-documented tribes in
which sexuality has taken many forms which in current Western
civilisation has been denied as criminal, including the incorporation
of children into portion of adult sexual life. I am against violence in
all forms and I find it extremely wrong if a powerful being, like an
adult, is violent against a less powerful being, like a child. A child
is also in a situation where adults often are sources of information
not just about the world, but also about themselves and about their own
lives. If, on the basis of lies and covert action an adult lures a
child into something on a false basis then this tastes of violence.
However, the current absolute condemnation of sex between children and
adults or between children and children has little grounding in
anything else but tradition. It is not offered as a refutable, ie,
scientific proposition.
While
I am in the
happy situation of finding more than enough
interesting sexual partners, models for painting, and partners in other
senses, which are adult, mature and above eighteen and all that, I know
nevertheless a great deal of what I myself felt and did as, say, a
thirteen-year old. It had no limits to it, and the girls in my class
surely agreed. Climbing in trees I reguarly got orgasm, not thinking of
it as anything having to do with other people, since kindergarten age.
The particular moments of experiencing arousal in the whole body on
encountering certain facets of other people's bodies took me to look to
painters who engaged in portraying such facets in a more advanced
fashion. Through this my artistic spirit was aroused. In doing computer
programming, I noticed that unless I was sexually happy my intelligence
withered. The grounding of each day in some kind of sexual activity,
even 'self-sex', in yoga, massage, dance and in sexually oriented
expressions also as painting eventually became something which provided
each day with the kind of healing harmony in which I could be a
dialogue partner with other people in a way that could be of advantage
to others. So my capacity to be compassionate was, in short, enhanced
by realizing the grounding in sexual energy as a grounding for all
life, not just some.
While
this is
something I can be completely honest about to myself, I
am still often shocked about the narrow-minded inculcations which seem
to drive the very young. The parents, schools, TV, and newspapers
engage in a common fundamentalistic irrefutable-sounding condemnation
of so many parts of the essential human energy that they, in effect,
irresponsibly deprive their individuals of a full respect for the whole
being. Of course, those who are fundamentalistically clinging to notion
of 'life after death' do so quite consciously: they want people to hate
themselves and their lives so as to love God more and love the next
life more and so as to give money, power and prestige to the priests
and imams furthering such nonsensical points of views.
To
me, then, the
role of the body in painting is this: it must be
sexually awakened and alive and enlivening for all who have the
willingness to respect the fullness of life as sexual. In this, they
will find that they also reconnect to their own hearts, that the paths
of ethics are enlightened and easier to follow, and that both health
and luck, the appetite for beautiful actions, and success coming from
golden means rather than from stinking means, are awakened for them.
*
How to listen to
the voice
of intuition
Each
body is
unique, different, changing all the time; it's alive, and
for a body to learn to listen to itself, and for the brain, also
unique, no other brain like it, to know what it means to pick up the
voice of intuition -- this is an art. The learning is beyond any 'how',
obviously. It is not a mere technique or method, there is no eightfold
path or fourfold truth but a constant learning, and in this learning we
must be in the role of the beginner. We must have the beginner's mind,
always sensitive, responsive.
So
what is it to
listen to the voice of intuition?
As
a poem cannot
explain another poem so cannot one person's intuition
tell another person of intuition. We cannot dictate it to one another
or impode it on one another. It is not about a curriculum, but about
the most important exploration a human being can ever undertake. It is
the basis for all the decisions, all the choices, all the motions,
actions, even also the basis of the feelings -- this, the issue of
listening to intuition.
What
is intuition?
Go to a dictionary or state your impossibilities,
with that I am not concerned. For intuition, as far as I can see, is
about possibilities. Anyone who asserts that intuition in some form is
impossible is merely preventing himself from a possibility and not
asserting a truth.
The
voice of
silence, the intelligence of love -- or intuition, the
tutoring from within, from one's own light, being a light to oneself --
whatever phrase we give to it, it is about the foundation of our life.
We must evoke or enable our inner silent intelligence, we must find out
what it means to be obedient to it, to let it speak.
Don't
come,
please, with an issue such as 'logic must have a say, too'.
For intuition is about listening and relating to everything and not
excluding anything. There is no conflict between rationality and
intuition for rationality or ratio, relationship or wholeness, is all
about living by intuition and, in a intuitive process, checking
intuitions, looking for logical consistencies and contradictions,
feeling over the rationality and the issues of reasoning. Nothing of
this is prevented if we understand that intuition is not I Ching, not
Tarot card, not Astrology, not this or that but a holistic flow of
feeling in which silence has its say.
We
go beyond
thought, that is the task in intuition.
What
is the
feeling that something is an intuition? How does it feel?
Is
it effort? You
see the importance of this question? We are now in
the negating mode, or the destilling mode. We ask a question so as to
purify our attention to what it is we are asking about. The attention
goes inward, to itself, purpose dissolves, and also illusions, false
assumptions. So that we see more clearly. We give space, have space,
make space and we comes from the enquiry with a much freer mind. Not
just much freer but free, free in its own whole sense.
So
is there effort
when there is intuition?
Is
there effort or
is effort merely a token of resistance?
Effort
involves a
conflict, a resistance between 'what is' and some
ideal, the 'what should be'. And intuition is something else, it flies
with its own energy. So you learn to listen to all these things, to
what has inertia and what is free from inertia, if we can put it that
way. Thought is matter, said J Krishnamurti. Thought-time can be
dissolved in meditation and then silence can come in; silence can
communicate something to thought if thought is silent. Do you see the
significance of this?
We
may try to
reason out some thing and because there can always be
more knowledge, it is clear that knowledge is limited and so we ask
instead: what does intuition say? And in that silence, leaving out all
the purposes, feeling freedom from the problem -- not thinking about
it, not being attached to any of the solutions we have portrayed
before, something erupts. It comes out. As grace, rather uninvited,
though we may have made a space for it through the question and leaving
the question alone, not worrying about it. Henry Poincare spoke of the
best intuitions coming at moments such as going on to the bus -- having
left the problem, after looked into it for a while. Not thinking about
it, the fresh sudden complete solution arrives effortlessly.
So
we must be
willing to set aside the quasi-solutions of thought, full
as they may be of inertia, of the sluggishness and pettiness of self.
We must not belittle life, not belittle the world, not make small or
petty what or who we are, what or who other people are. It is not us
against them but a question of life relating to life through also our
own being. Right?
In
asking these
questions each day anew we awake to a life beyond the
self. Intuition can come and be the basis. What if an intuition is
wild, seems wild, seems dangerous?
So
we must go slow
and learn what distinguishes a holistic, quiet,
warm-temperature-in-stomach intuition from something which has the
coldness of hatred or violence or cheating about it. We must go slow
and let the truth detection of our own nerves reflect back to our
minds, listening to the symphony of life as it unfolds.
You
may get a
rather wild intuition and you ask yourself: can it really
be so? Being cautious, not afraid, but just unwilling to take stupid
risks, you don't adopt the intuition as a decision right away because
it may be polluted by ego, by illusions, by other things which are not
of the issue it appears to be about. It may be right to walk a little
in some other direction then change.
Some
intuitions
are so as to help you define an outline for an
important project or action: it takes you to some excess in order to
see that the excess is unnecessary; it shows you the golden means by
first taking you to some extremes.
Some
intuitions
are given you so as to bring about a feature in your
life which is only naturally available if you are innocent about the
fact that you are going to change direction, get a new intuition,
around the next corner so to speak. You bring about events and social
interactions by adopting also fleeting intuitions not quite knowing
that they are fleeting. The not-knowingness means that you can be frank
and yet change opinion when it is right to change opinion. It is not
always a virtue to be steadfast, if steadfastness leads to stagnation.
The
wild
intuitions may come again and again but between each time you
have worked to see whether it can be done without taking a stupid risk.
You don't want to waste a hand or finger on going to the top of that
mountain so you are careful, compassionate to all life, never accepting
violent means, always the passifist, always gracious to others and
never accepting any form of mafia-methods ever. That is most important,
and if anyone has done so in the past one must pray for forgiveness
again and again and leave it open to life to give oneself a new grace.
So
the past goes,
it is transformed when you face it without illusion,
without trying to fake it. You give attention to what you are and what
you have done and know that there is a current of forgiveness in
humanity -- humanity forgiving itself -- and this current is most real
and most important. One must not toss away the issue of forgiveness.
One must be able to let go of the past and face it, have
reconcilliation. Even politically, as the twentieth-century great
politician Nelson Mandela carried out, with his 'truth and
reconsilliation' committees, leading to a rather nonviolent
transgression from dictatorship to democracy in South Africa. That is a
spiritual approach, and it can work. It must work, in the long run, it
is the only thing that work. And if it is the only thing that works in
the long run, then it is a thing of the heart, it is then the only
righteous action. It is right now because it is right in the long run.
You see we mustn't divide the two?
Intuition,
then,
is about a righteous life, not trying to impose goals
from the ego and try to make the universe fulfill the little selfish
ambition. Rather, the goals as well as the means must come from this
flow of meditation over the harmonious love that is a potential in all
living beings. It is not excuse that many live according to something
else; it is our duty to emphasize the sense of enlightenment, not just
for me or us or you but for life, on behalf of life, not dividing soul
from soul.
One
must let the
mind dance, training it to speak spontaneously with
certainty of things not known consciously; this certainty must be
challenged decently, in a dialogue with oneself. When reasoning and
experience suggest strongly that the inner certainty is wrong, one must
meditate and not get dogmatic on behalf of one's inner voice. It is
insanity to disregard one's inner voice or not to activate it if one
does not have it. It is sanity to be in constant affirmation of
wholeness and listen to how silence employs your own thought. In this,
coffeine may be a more creative potent factor than the stimulant in
black tea; in a snap, one may quip that tea is for control-manic
people, but coffee for the creative ones.
If
the activation
leads to disharmonious statements from within, it
means one has a filthy preconscious mind, and so it must be purified.
Read life-affirming books with more than just a positive moral; change
the images on the wall; go for long walks; talk not on phone much and
relate to harmonious people and do not quarrel with those who are
disharmonious; visualize healing etc etc. It is a passionate work and
the result is a joy which surpasses all forms of conventional happiness.
If
beauty comes
from within, from the dance within -- if, indeed, the
shape of the body and the face flows from the dance of cells which in
turn moves according to the mind-potential, as it unravels from year to
year -- then the goodness of doing right, the ethics in one's whole
sense of being, becomes, as the years go by, the esthetics of one's
face and whole demanour. Let vanity go but let also the mirror teach
one about ethics, about refinement -- with the intent of beauty, and
indeed also of radiating such, there is something of a golden rod
showing the path of right action; an action that preserves a sense of
deep happiness though it may not always prove to be whether polite nor
satisfactory from the point of view of narrow self.
Beauty
and
sexuality goes together. Can sex be regarded as an addiction
along addictions to alchohol or drugs? Or is sex, as sex, pure and
healthy, but rather the question is: what is the context which sex
occurs within? Is that a context that is, in itself, as action,
beautiful?
*
Sketch of a
mathematical
insight into
infinity
Counting
is a
rather complex process involving degrees of similarities
and asserting associations between a stable set of signs with an
arbitrary assembly, such as when we say that the signs (or tokens,
rather) I, II, III, IIII, IIIII, are to a high degree similar
to I, II, III, IIII, IIIII and can be associated to,
say, a, b, c, d, e.
Are
the
signs I, II, III, IIII, IIIII just strongly similar
to I, II, III, IIII, IIIII or in fact identical, which means
'remaining the same'? Even a typescript font on a computer screen
or on a printed page contain innumerable differences, of
course, if seen with a magnifying lens. So any assertion of
identity is subjective.
Mathematics
lies
in the perception of the most general processes of
perception, as applied to such associations of a fixed assembly with an
arbitrary assembly as we just looked at. In all questions of
perception, 'looking again' has a direct authority whereas
reference or memory of 'past looking' has really no authority at
all. For mathematics is not about memory.
In
particular,
this means that any reference to a fixed set of socalled
"problems" cannot express anything of an essential contemplation of
mathematics.
In
any perceptive
process, questions of domains in focus versus a
possibly shifting context are bound to arise at regular or irregular
intervals.
Unless
you believe
in revelation, there is no final, basic,
standard, ultimate or finite set of categories from which to start as
to the question of foreground vs background, process vs content,
context vs domain in focus. In particular, the perceptive process
underlying mathematics allows for no sharp domain "definition" since
that would put an arbitrary limit on perception.
Most
generally,
then, the borders of the domains of relevant perceptive
activity of mathematics are not only unknown, but should remain unknown
in the sense of consciously part of the sense of the unknowing.
In
particular,
while from an impatient "tools" perspective it would be,
perhaps, for some fascinating to attempt to delineate a socalled
"field" of mathematics from an imagined distinct or semidistinct
"field" of physics, the most appropriate advice may be to refrain from
all such delineation, perhaps.
On
the other hand,
if you believe in revelation (say, that of Georg
Cantor when he postulated the definitions of certain imagined
collections of numbers), then you must face the question of how
you would relate to the situation of having a perception that's at odds
with the revelation you believe in. Would you then automatically
regard it as a misperception? The most basic approach of science
is to brush such attitudes aside as banal.
Perceptually,
if
we count by such rather self-explaining numbers
as I, II, III, etc, adding a mark for each
additional number sought, the width of the sign is in correspondance
with its intended meaning.
Clearly,
if
we can always go beyond any particular limit as to
the highest number by simply adding a mark, then there is no maximum
width either.
Let
us now ask
what we could perceive to be the sense of all possible
numbers given the type of number and number-construction as involved in
I, II, III, etc. I ask the reader to 'look again' if the reader has a
lot of memorized proposals as to such questions in mind.
As
has been
pointed out by many, notable also Wittgenstein, the
apprehension of a "rule" from an example process is a question of
perception and thus contains some openness. That is, we are left
with flux no matter how hard we try to designate things.
One
of the
startling experiences for a very young individuals learning
more and more about counting, say, with number entities like
I, II, III, IIII, IIIII may come when faced
with the question: what is the highest number you can imagine?
Humanity
may still
be as a child when it comes to these questions
despite the self-righteous, arrogant, over- certain proposals as to the
nature of the answers to such questions.
One
way would be
to say that given any limit, we can always
construct a number whose value is one greater. This concept of the
'flexible limit' seems to apply to the construction process, and
as such, also to the sense of a possible whole collection of all
numbers. I call into question as to whether this is an exhaustive
characteristics, however. If someone says, 'certainly the
flexible limitconcept is enough to characterize the collection of all
whole numbers uniquely and completely', then we can, based on the
general sense of mathematics as a perceptive process, ask for the
perception that led to this great claim on something as mysterious as a
collection of all possible numbers.
If
the answer
is, "see how fruitful it is to make such a
claim, see what wonderful bridges we can make etc", then we
are asked to perceive of the effects of asserting a claim. And
while these effects may indeed be wonderful, that is hardy to give a
perceptual foundation for the statement. Rather, a justification
of something by referring to its effects involves guiding attention
away from this something. This may still involve perception but now
perception is limited to effects rather than content of a statement.
This is at odds with the essentially unbounded nature of perception
called for in the most general approach initially sketched here for
mathematics.
To
go back to the
perception of the counting process, and of the
question: what would the sense of the collection of all possible
numbers I, II, III, etc, mean, let us ask, even
though it has been answered a million times, is this a finite or
infinite collection?
The
flexible limit
concept shows that any finite limit can be
transcended. So it seems we can negate the possibility that the
sense of this collection is finite. In saying that it is infinite, what
do we mean by this?
In
other words,
what is the deeper meaning of et cetera, in the
context of I, II, III, etc?
Let
us call into
attention that in perception, flux is law, and
stability an appearance. We should not get shocked or overwhelmed
if our attempts at understanding the full implications of 'et cetera'
somehow involve movement. For even the perception of the
similarity of I, II, III, IIII, IIIII, IIIIII with I,
II, III, IIII, IIIII, IIIIII is an active process with its own
natural inborn uncertainties, opennesses, and fluctuations.
We
'know', I think
we can say at this stage, that the flexible limit is
one feature of the sense of the whole collection of numbers beginning
with I, II, III, etc. But what of other features? We can
say: 'not finite', but what does this infinity really imply?
Rather
as simple
equations may reveal infinite orders of unique
structure when turned upon itself as in the wellknown case of
Mandelbrot as concerns the computer-generated 'Mandelbrot
fractal', perhaps the counting process does indeed contain unique
infinite structure when studied more closely.
Let
us not lean on
past "authorities" for there are none in the field
of mathematics. The authority is the process of dialogic play in
perception itself.
The
exceeding
simplicity in writing
.
.
.
I I I
I I
I
to
indicate the
growth 'upwards, and to the right', may show no more of
the actual process than, say, an initial sketch of the Mandelbrot
fractal before it is magnified in one of its border regions. Or
it may say as little as the Mandelbrot equation compared to the whole
fractal. In honoring the nature of perception the scientific
startingpoint is to assert "we don't know".
We
see that in I,
II, III, ... or in
.
.
.
I I I
I I
I
there
is no upward
limit. What else do we see? We can see, for
instance, that the set {I, II} can be characterized as to size by
II, whereas the set {I, II, III} by III, and in general,
that {I, II, III, .. n} can be characterized by n. This we can call the
"self-reflective size property". The self-reflective size property of
the collection of numbers I, II, III may be imagined to work for I, II,
III etc, where "etc" signifies extension in an absolutely nonlimited
sense. However, this is a big postulate, and while it seems
very likely, I would not take the stance that it can be "taken
for granted".
The
self-reflective size property for the collection
I
I
I I
I I I
I I
I
can
be said to be
that the freshest, biggest addition to the collection
echoes the size of the collection.
It
would be
surprising (I think) to find that the self-reflective size
property works only for finite sets but not for infinite sets.
And yet the twentieth century knows scarcely a math text book that
speaks of the collection {1, 2, 3, ...} as a set whose infinite size is
mirrored in even one of is members. The signs 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ...
can be argued to be merely more complex but tight ways of writing I,
II, III, IIII, IIIII, ... for both extend in width eventually.
So
since we are
now in a position to focus clearly on a perceptual
question about which there may be an interesting disagreement with
textbook authorities of the past, and which is conceptually, at least,
foundational to thinking about numbers in mathematics and thus about
mathematics in general, let us restate the issue.
We
see that I, II,
III, ... or
.
.
.
I I I
I I
I
has
a feature in
that, at each step, as far as I can see right
now, the amount of members at each point is indeed the newest
addition. We can now look at the three dots signifying, "let the
process go on".
Let
me also point
out that, in the context of the present
research, the words "set" and "collection" are used rather
interchangably and informally, utilizing a daily life language
sense rather than any definition in which certainty as to what is
talked about is assumed.
To
focus the
question of the infiniteness involved, let us see
that there is a perceptual advantage in writing I, II, III, IIII,
... over 1, 2, 3, 4, ... which is clearly brought forward in
.
.
.
I I
I I
I I I
I I
I
in
any discussion
involving a comparison between the number added most
recently and the actual size of the set so far. For series such as 1,
2, 3, .., 9, 10, 11, .., 99, 100, 101, .., 999, 1000, 1001, ... must be
interpreted to a larger extent rather than merely "read" and that
complexifies the process.
As
far as the
counting goes, I don't think we can easily imagine
any sensorimotoric physical-empirical process actually constructing an
infinite collection which exists physically for our senses. The
notion of the 'transcendent mental' must be brought in, as if by
science fiction, to allow us to see what is conceptually
meaningful while sensorimotorically impractical.
These
things may
sound trivial but in my experience slowness and
exacting reports on the actual processes of perception provide a better
background for generating interesting new perceptions than any amount
of footnotes and authority renderings.
We
can see, to go
on, that in
.
.
.
I I
I I I
I I
I I
I I I
I I
I
we
let the three
dots indicate the growth of an infinite triangle whose
upperside width equals its leftside height at all points in the growth
process, given regular spacing of the marks constituting each number.
Geometrically, then, this is an "argument" in favour of the
self-reflective size property of all sets equivalent to {1, 2, 3, ...}.
We have not
yet, however, pushed the question of perceiving what
the sense of having a truly infinite collection actually means.
If
at this stage
we proceed to make other sets, such as that of numbers
with a decimal dot notation, we are likely to end up with Cantors R
>> N where R is all the "real numbers", whereas N is all the
"natural numbers", implying the notion of the transfinite and so
on. But since we have not really looked at what the full infinite
set of numbers 1, 2, 3, ... or I, II, III, ... actually is,
conceptually speaking, it may be premature to begin to utilize members
of the set N in "arguments" such as the socalled "diagonal argument"
putting size(N) as less than size(R).
Even
the
formulation of a socalled "real number" like pi = 3.14159...
begs the question of what the infinity of the three dots really is all
about.
My
earlier
investigations led me to discard all trust in the "easy"
definition of the set "N of all natural numbers being {1, 2, 3, ...}"
which is the basis for thousands of volumes of mathematical thought.
That is of course a factor inciting me, in this dialude, to be
extremely cautious in asserting anything at all about the process of
counting and about notions of collecting all possible numbers.
However, even if we had no prior reason to be sceptical about a
particular feature of such a process, why not just take the
stance of the fruitfulness of such perceptive care in general? It may
be a lot more to uncover.
So
once we
concider that at each point in the construction, from
I
I I
I I
I
to
I
I
I I
I I I
I I
I
to
I
I
I I I
I I
I I
I I I
I I
I
etc,
the height
equals the width of this triangle, we can
perhaps, with luck, jump correctly into perceiving the mental
phenomenon involving the "et cetera" of this process indefinitely.
It
would seem,
wouldn't it, very hard to argue that at the completion
of the "et cetera to infinity" (whatever that really means), the
width has lost connection with the height, and now the height is
infinite whereas the width is merely a "flexible limit". This
perceptive argument calls into question the adherence to the notion of
the limit (the flexible limit) when one is trying to understand an
infinite process.
Indeed,
it
seems easier to assert that it is likely that if this
"et cetera to infinity" is "completed", somehow, we no longer merely
have finite numbers and that which we have instead is somehow (also)
infinite.
What
does this
imply?
Put
very simply,
it tears down the idea that the set of all finite
whole numbers can be considered a clear idea. Without this as a clear
idea, it implies that whenever a set of this type is involved in a
so-called proof, the proof must be reconsidered.
One
way to
reconsider the proof is to admit that the defined set may
contain all finite whole numbers but it is not limited to these. Since
the process of creating the set allows allow for a flexible limit, it
is unlikely that we will find that it is but one nonfinite whole
member. Rather, the likelihood is that as soon as we open for even one
nonfinite member, we allow for an infinity of nonfinite members.
Further
analysis
of these themes, which I have not included here, shows
that any attempt to make a system out of infinities involve its own
kind of finiteness, and so easily involve illusions.
As
a physicist,
one could surmise that reality must have a more solid
conceptual basis in the infinite than in the finite, if one has, as
Einstein, a trust in the rationality of the whole of the universe, but,
unlike Einstein, a distrust in the finite as a result from this
succinct study.
I
call for a
complete revision of all mathematical texts which start
with a definition of 'the set of natural numbers' or 'the set of whole
numbers' as if it were a trivial manner, if the above is correct. I
think it is, however this is not something I expect it is easy to get
institutionlized (ie, academic) support for. (Indeed, I did not get
support for it in a concrete case which I have explained somewhere at
the library section of www.yoga4d.com.) Rather, the feeling that one
may get, in browsing some of the literature around Cantor's work, is
that it is considered to be so canonical that any doubt of it is
categorized as rather moot. In contrast, I find it ripe and rich and
promising, and I am sure that, in some decade, plenty of healthy
rethinking about logic will flow from just this work as presented here
-- though it is, of course, pretentious to say so. It is, at least, a
gut feeling I have.
To
put it very
short: there is no mathematics. For two millenia, we
have heard philosophers say that 'in the empirical world, there are
uncertainties; but in the mathematical realm, there is the purity of
certainty' and similar nonsense. There is uncertainty everywhere, also
in mathematics, for it is all about perception. It is always uncertain
whether a proof is a proof. The universe is unfinished. Mathematics is
just a bag of tricks. And no trick is garanteed to work always. So
there is no mathematics, only heuristics. That is the conclusion --
which is, at the same time, a nonconclusion, a total mind-opener, a
liberation from the gullible attitude towards dogmatic pompous
declarations.
In
this way, the
very notion of infinity is uncertain as well, not just
finiteness; and the distinction between the digital and the analog is
not certain in itself. At some level, like a hundred 'implicate orders'
beneath the explicate order, it may be that reality is perfectly
digital. For only the digital is ever-new, in the sense: it has no
accumulation, no past.
*
Colors in
painting
When
I speak of an
'alphabeth' in colors that a painter may take as a
basis, I do not mean that this alphabeth should be adhered to in a way
that feels narrow-minded. Rather, it is a preferred basis. The colours
may be mixed, in a process which leads to an infinity of variation
between them, and there may be interactions with what is in the
physical canvas (or whatever) on which they are used, and sometimes
entirely different colors may be brought in. Nevertheless, it can be of
an advantage, I feel, to realize the joy of having a limited yet
somehow full set of colors, in which a sense of infinity may be
displayed.
Just
think of the
impressionists in France and other places, painting
summerly paintings with shining bright colours indicating rivers and
green and yellow country-sides, blue skies, pink girls and what not.
They lifted up home after home with a painting style feeling so fresh
it could be compared to fruits, and perhaps a piano played some Chopin
while the little girls did their ballet excerises. You may call it an
escape from the horrors of the world but then, what's wrong with that?
If the escape actually works? If it really gives harmony and peace, so
that people can create something truly constructive, brought forth by
the compassion wielded by this harmony inside their hearts?
However
we like
it, most painters who produced a great deal have had a
preferred color alphabeth; some of these alphabeth we may not be sure
of, as in the case of the arguments over the restaurations of ancient
paintings by Michelangelo and others. Did he really use pink? What of
Rembrandt, is it really not the case that they were in love with brown
and black but that it is merely due to a magnificant fading that we see
certain color shades today?
Politically,
there
may be reasons to avoid certain colours, as if: but
politics must never take any precedence over the question of what can
raise the human spirit, elevate our souls, make our minds open to the
glory of the greater universe. We must look aside from what some
politicians have come to call themselves, whether blue black or violet,
and ask: what is it that most appeal to my heart -- me being someone
who perhaps have a taste different from any other, yet somehow in
attunement with the infinite -- and work it out from there. Just as an
orchid may have its own color code and spells out its symmetries and
asymmetries by means thereof.
There
are quantum
fluctuations, we hear from the reports of the
physicists studying things in their laboratories. The greeks some 500
years before Christ would have been shocked, startled, they would have
had to tear apart a lot of their works if they had a roundtrip in the
quantum laboratories and in the cosmological laboratories with
telescopes and movies of novas and so on. They would have had to have a
translator with them, and probably a great deal of 'debriefing' both
before and after. Then they would have to say: Movement is king! Long
live the new king! And all their things about the infinite static would
have to be tossed away like toilet paper.
The
quantum
fluctuations, moreoever, is akin to the role of rhythm and
movement which I personally would attribute to what I have elsewhere
indicated may be an 'infinite number'. For they have, don't they, these
fluctuations, something ambigious about them. They don't tend to move
exactly according to any specific scheme but if studied through
thousands and thousands exactly repeated experiments their very
different behaviour each time can perhaps be summed up statistically.
And so we see that any interesting interaction between human beings --
why not look to the acting feats by people such as Woody Allan and
Peter Sellers -- is full of ripples of the ambigiously fluctuating.
So
we see, through
the metaphor or intuitive apprehension, of these
fluctuations, that there are symphonies of what Carl Gustav Jung called
'synchronicities' here, and I feel any good painter would do well to
listen to them. I can say without insult, because I am born in Norway
myself, that the Norwegian painter Edward Munch did not listen much to
these synchronicities -- for he kept on painting his pains and the
pains kept on coming to his life, leading to mental trouble and so on.
You get the life that you paint.
The
black, spring
green (or leaf green), and golden, that I combine in
the paintings of flowing dancers is a colour alphabeth that I just
might still be using very long time indeed after this has been written.
In fact, the idea has been to find something which can be a perfectly
stable basis for all the coherent fluctuating dances that I wish to
express -- and I foresee an infinity of them!
In
painting, we
have the concept of One Of Each, we might playfully
make the computer-like acronym OOE, to say: a painting is absolutely
different from the digital. The digital world, with its digitalism
streaks in human culture, has only parroting, aping, imitation, to
offer. Where there are many of each, we do not have the analogue; where
we do not have the analogue, we do not have reality, but something
which merely pokes on reality. These pokes on reality include the
digital texts which we may generously offer to one another. In a
healthy interactivity economy and in a coherent open society, we do not
patent digital items but give them freely, and in addition make
analogue items in a spiritual way, by hand etc, for which we can take a
solid price.
Digital
generosity
can then go hand in hand with analogue economy.
Digital generosity can be extended to all forms of generosity which
does not involve substance, including giving talks, dance performances,
having conversations etc. In addition to the substanceless activities
which give deep meaning, we can create, craft tokens of the same
generosity with a substance characterized by OOE -- one of each. The
OOE is what really has a price and, in a sense, there is no such things
as 'replacability' in the analogue realm.
A
compassionate
anarchist like myself find it, in the same vein,
untastely to 'employ' a person, which is, in Martin Buber-terms, to
treat a person as if the person were an 'it'. Rather, a living organism
is infinitely OOE and there is no possibility either of employing nor
of disemploying. All sorts of ownership, or near-ownership, or buying
of another persons time, smacks of a slave- and fascistoid attitude. In
realizing this, we move towards the artistic society, in which the
compassion generated by good works, and the luck generated by generous
actions, becomes the coherent measuring rod.
Of
course, this
all involves a world view shift: from the view that
nothing matters much (apart from a comparison with goals), to the point
of view that every action has infinite consequences that directly and
immediately strike back on the person that emits this action if it is
not generous; and if it is a generous action, it builds up the good
synchronicity potential of this person. Ie, luck builds up. One might
put it into the form of a motto: an atom of generosity is an atom of
luck. Much generosity is much luck. And luck is a real thing, not
chance, nor a ruleboundedness, but a potential of coherence, a
coherence wrought by the quantum nonlocalities which weave together all
of the universe. One may not believe in this, but it is possible to
explore it in a refutable sense: is there, or is there not such a thing
as luck? Is it, or is it not, correlated to the presence of a basically
generous attitude in what one is doing?
But
to come to the
state of generosity, even in making artworks (so
that each painting is a token of luck and an offering of good health
and luck to all who owns it, sees it etc), one must address each item
in oneself of frustrated emotions. These frustrated emotions basically
have elements of comparison in them. One can discover this in a
refutable way by introducing a novel comparison and see how some
emotions radically shifts at once: for instance, one can compare how
much one after all has with someone else. But if comparison can change
the emotion, then it may be that if comparison is dissolved, then the
frustrated emotion will dissolve as a whole; ie, that it has no other
ground than this.
In
a proper
self-study, one acknowledges that one's negative emotions
are there, if they are there, rather than brushing them under the
carpet. Then one proceeds both with a particular investigation of each
emotion, as well as with a general investigation, of emotionality in
general. In dissolving jealousy, envy, bitterness, rage, frustration,
loneliness, fear, etc, one must look into each issue directly, and also
in a general way.
For
instance, in
looking into fear, one must ask oneself not just of
what one is frightened of, and guess at it, work it out, but also go
further and ask for the realities in the matter, if any. If one find
that one actually should engage in an avoidance-action, one must then
proceed and ask whether a constant fear or anxiety (personally, I would
not think it is fruitful to assert a strong division between the two)
is a proper avoidance, or whether it is actually not an avoidance at
all, merely an irrelevant constant noise inside oneself. Which is to
say, there may be snakes (or whatever) in the dark (in certain areas,
there are, in fact), but it may not help to go around with a constant
anxiety in oneself. Rather, one must be watchful (perhaps, if there is
a reality to what one has fear of), but this watchfulness should not at
all lead to a noise or a frustrated state of mind. If it does, one can
affirm, on the proper stage in one's own self-study, that worry is
pointless, be relaxed, just be watchful where it makes sense and ignore
it beyond that. This is an example.
Have
I myself had
fear, since I speak of this issue? I have had fear
just as I have had cold, and I think it is important for anyone to have
gone to the limits of one's own mental abilities occasionally, such as
by denying oneself sleep (or much sleep) for several days in a row, and
see what happens. Of course I have done this, more or less on purpose,
several times; and of course I have seen every kind of psychic state in
myself, and sometimes it took a day or even five to get properly out
of. With meditation, yoga, dialogic tools such as writing, one can
always restore harmony, and with plenty of walking and healthy eating,
the intellectual insights becomes shared with all the body rather than
there being a strong division between the two. I would say that anyone
who does this, instead of avoiding going to mental extremes, is on the
path to evoke the artist in herself.
Women
wanting to
become artists have, traditionally, an extra challenge
or two, compared to men: since women due to certain physical natural
aspects such as roundedness are the natural object of esthetics, in
several ways, women must adopt some of the hunter-attidue of men with
regard to other women in order to relay the ecstasy of beauty in an
artistic form. This may have been tougher in earlier times but the
recent decades of willingness to assert the essential bi-sexuality of
all people (as part of a pan-sexuality that is also iso-sexual, iso-
meaning 'the same', ie, for oneself), should lead to a radical
awakening on this part. In addition, I am aware of some scientific
experiments on hormones which might indicate that the division of the
hormones into male and female types are, perhaps, a great deal more
complex than before thought. For instance, testoterone seems to be a
sexual hormone for females, and there are weak indications that the
converse is also true, that oestrogene is a sexual hormone for males.
Since
a person
must not try to be a politician at the same time as
being an artist, it is important to quench all fears of bi-sexuality at
once, for a female artist: to step radically out of any condemnation in
this area, and evoke a willingness to enjoy pornography as elementary
lessons in interesting anatomy about women. This entails, of course, a
stepping out of the comparing ego that desires to be better than
everyone else. The comparing ego would destroy the esthetics of
anything one does.
Furthermore,
to
evolve such a radical transformation of oneself towards
the artist, one must realize that one of the last places that such
transformations are likely to be echoed, are in the socalled academic
artistic institutions.
*
The role of
slenderness
and the question
of whether
health is
attractive
As
Moshe
Feldenkrais suggested, in his physical training programmes,
the feeling of what is 'natural' may be conditioned, influenced,
affected by habit and various impulses from the environment. To come to
what is truly natural, also in the sense of healthy and supportive of
life and joy, he suggested that we must teach the body to teach itself
how to find the natural action spontaneously, after the habit has been
unlearned. His subtle language speaks of a strong mind with deep
insight and I have not studied his work enough as yet to account for it
more just here.
However,
what
Feldenkrais taught in the area of physical movement I
feel is relevant to dance, yoga, massage, and even further into more
psychological tasks such as computer programming, the writing of
philosophy, and thinking about life in general.
Is
it healthy to
be slender? I happen to think that sex is not vulgar
but that being fat is vulgar. Because I am in love with movement and
flexibility, and the shape of the human being when she can move about
freely and act joyously, without any limits brought by styles of
living, I see slenderness as a token for health. The amount of
illness-potential associated with fatness suggested by numerous
scientific reports is huge and so I wonder how it can be considered
irrefutable by some that one should simply accept and give in to
whatever fatness there is, instead of daring to challenge it strongly
and speak of it as an enemy of a free and natural life. So I am not
embarrassed by painting slender dancer girls and I know it is a
potential of every individual, given an atheletic discipline with
regard to what is eaten and how exercise is done, to be a graceful
dancer in some way.
Now
is it so that
health is attractive? If we by 'attractive' means
'interesting' or 'can be an object of desire' then the answer seems to
be: No, not necessarily so. For anything at all, even death, can be
made into an object of desire by sufficient sick conditioning. However,
if we ask for an attractiveness that goes deep and is pervasive, so as
to evoke the heart, then perhaps the healthy and the whole is the only
thing that is attractive.
So
the exploration
into intuition can take us into questions of what is
worth having passion for; it can make us realize certain conditionings
and show us the path to uncondition ourselves. In dehypnotizing
ourselves from something like ungratefulness it is possible to affirm,
suggestively, to oneself, 'gratefulness' (as Patanjali proposed). Is it
possible to destill the essence of true attractiveness? I leave this as
a question for the reader.
Yet
I would like
to add: it is my clear perception that a person,
adult, who spends a decade in working on a non-tantric basis is
literally killing himself or herself. There is little left of a person
who is not actively pursuing the erotic every day, in a tasteful sense,
connected to a feeling of awakening and intuition. The only way of real
genuine rejuvenation from within is to engage, tastefully, the erotic
in every minute of one's awareness and presence. The shock of seeing
who one is, in the mirror after wasting one's days in this or that
company or self-centered work, the shock of seeing the ego-marks on
one's face, should make one get rid of all meat-eating, all lack of
circulation, all lack of exercise, all lack of exploration; the pain of
it should make one realize the utter danger of being corrupt, so that
all corrupt work is laid aside; so that one awakes to the truth of
holistic living and becomes a constant healing factor with regard to
all, and also oneself.
*
Passion, energy,
sex
and freedom from
attachments
With
the quality
of refutability, or humility, wrought into our
statements about our psyches, let us enquire, think about life, so as
to come to greater freedom, clarity, love, joy. We do not start by
asserting an impossibility. Nor do we start by asserting that all good
things are merely due to coincidence, or that life is inherently
unjust, or that one has been born on the wrong side or anything of
that. Society may be terrible but life is greater than any society and
your life is greater than the social. You are also a cosmic being, a
being unto yourself, and there is a greatness in that, no matter what
newspapers say or don't say, no matter what parents may want or not
want you to become.
So
can we know
ourselves?
To
know ourselves
means, surely, also to understand something of
emotions.
Emotions
are not
merely a genetic thing, not merely a damp bottled up,
but something generated by attachment and moved by preconscious
assumptions and images. You can have an image about something unreal
and it can generate an emotion. You can tell yourself to like something
you don't like and after a year or much before you start liking it.
So
what is the
influence of parents and upbringing? Are we slaves of
our early environment? If we are, can we see that and so step out of
that slavery? We can, can't we? If you see very clearly what is going
on, slowly and carefully, you do not have to entertain the kind of
emotions you were conditioned to have.
It
is the duty of
parents to set children free from them and from the
environment, free to live life full of love and optimism and joy, a
life on behalf of the future and of responsibility, the kind of
responsibility that has generosity and happiness in it, not the dreary
kind of responsibility toward a bible or a tradition.
Can
there be a
passion which has no seeds of attachment in it? A
passion born of a bonding trust with all life, not just pieces of life?
Attachment,
how
does it begin? If we explore this issue we may find
that it is at the root of practically every human problem. Attachment
leads to a crushed psyche. People may argue that attachment is
important, that it is a sign of love, but let us look at it calmly --
there may be something far deeper than attachment which can come into
our life. Love may be something radically different than attachment.
You
walk past a
car, it has a gleaming shine to it, you imagine how it
is to sit in its seats and float over the environment, feel free, go
somewhere far, with a lovely voluptous companion beside you, a guitar
in the back seats -- or maybe it was a two-seater. You imagine this and
there is a rush, a flow of pleasure, it saturates your body and you
feel a tingling in your back. Then if you give the whole pleasure a
full moment of awareness, attend to it, see to it that the
pleasurecomes, it is there, and it goes away, then there is no residue
as a seed of desire or attachment.
However,
if you
experience a great pleasure, perhaps in orgasm, and you
let the images combine with the pleasure and quiet preconscious
thoughts start assembling around it making it into a nervous structure,
then there is more than a sense of beauty there: there is also a sense
of attachment. Of suffering, of pain, of not endless hatred but
possibly lots of hatred because an attachment is something that defends
itself in the mind, like a virus, is it not?
If
you think love
and attachment is the same thing then let me ask you:
is love something you give or is it something you crave? If it is
something you give, then is it something you give to an actual
individual or to your own favorite image of this individual? You give
it to the actual individual? Then what if this individual behaves
different than your attachment -- you follow? That the person behaves
not in according with your expectation? Then will you continue to give?
Then you are not attached, if you give and continue to give, if you are
generous and continue to be generous, if you have love and give space
and embrace lovingly no matter what happens, no matter if you are
turned down yourself. But if you cling and crave and give only on a
premise, then that a limited thing, is it not? It is of the ego if you
crave more than give. And if you really give you must cleanse and
purify the mind of all stains of such things as lead to hate and
immense self-pity.
If
someone tries
to think positively but at the same time nurtures
greed and attachment, there will be a lot of constant disappointment
and pain going on. This may lead to an obsessive positive thinking
which looses touch with the inner tyranny of depression and evil
hatred. The splitting of the mind can be seen in the body as an
accumulation of fat and lack of grace in movement, and other strange
things with the body not typical of health. To remedy this, we must be
willing to say -- yes, let us intend the positive, but let us also be
creative about words so as to fetch the negative current and do
something with it.
We
can use words
to give attention rather than divert attention. And so
the quest for a real passion, a real energy, which has not been tainted
by attachment and the boredom involved in attachment is important. Do
we see this, not as a theory, not as a mere intellectual idea -- do we
see it now, in the very moment of thinking about it, so that we are
also free?
Then
what is sex?
Can a girl have an immense lust and satisfaction and
pleasure in having great deep orgasms with a boy and then be free from
it? Or must the genetic background, the environment saying -- don't be
a slut! -- the parents saying, 'it could be a child, so hold onto the
boy' -- can you step out of the zillion assumptions surrounding sex,
and not make a problem of it?
It
may be a little
easier for boys than girls to go from a sexual
experience to another with not too great accumulation of attachment
because the implications of begetting a child comes more dramatically
for girls, since it is within them. With these implications it is only
natural that they take it a little more seriously.
So
the religious
systems, in their greed for power over individuals,
have largely institionalized prostitution in the form of marriage and
hopes to control individuals through this and other tasteless ways,
such as the Christian churches surrounded by tombs.
In
all their
tastelessness, religious systems have mostly taken a
stance against the freedom of sexuality and urged people to button it
up, lock it up. For those who say that they believe in Jesus let them
ask themselves: is it the words of Jesus that you believe in -- because
they were rather free and anarchistic -- or is it Paulus and Augustine
and their pumping up of the Jesus-character that they believe in?
Every
flower, the
joy of God expressed as Nature, is a token of
sexuality; sensuality is intrinstic in the beauty of the divine, as any
meditating person can feel when in the presence of peaceful wild
Nature. Why should sexuality be read as anything less but God's wings,
a heightened state of awareness, a deeper touch with our own buddhahood?
Energy
and humour
of a human being, health and intelligence -- is it
not all connected to a very active sex-drive? Should not a person
masturbate many times a day? Should we not actively teach each other
how to stay completely pure and healthy and childless while having many
sex partners?
All
pursuit of
human happiness must base itself, I feel, on a
willingness to distinguish between feelings born of silence and
emotions born of attachment. To the former belongs generosity,
forgiveness, gratefulness, care, love in a divine sense,
responsibility, wholeness, beauty and countless nuances all
characterised by compassion and empathy. To the latter belongs the
cognitively driven mediate emotions, the reactions stemming from an
immature psyche.
If
we harbour
bitterness or hate, then we must admit to the fact, speak
of it to ourselves, in our own private exploration space, and not hide
it. Then we must, I feel, explore the grounds for these emotions.
Instead of trying to convince oneself not to have them, let us bring
ourselves in connection with some perhaps false grounds for having them
-- not calling them false at first, but just seeing them.
When
we are in
touch with the grounds for bitterness it is possible to
see that these grounds are false and that will aid the emotion in
dissolving. When the noise of hate vanishes, the feeling of joy and its
intuition or intuitive intelligence comes.
To
do this, we
must reconsile ourselves with the fact that in any
processes involving consciousness, or mind, or emotion, there is such a
thing as a combination of matter and subtler forms of energy, and it
takes time or duration to change it. There is a way to speed the
processes of duration, and that is dance or dance-like states in which
harmony is nurtured. So a foundation for a fruitful healing or release
of negative embittered energy is a nurturing of classical harmonious
music, walking in nature, self-massage, yoga, dance, vegetarian food,
candle-lights, and harmonious fairy tale-like TV programs, and so on
and so forth. Good artworks grounded in harmony may be of important
help, too. (Indeed my own paintings in yellow (shining), spring green
and black have this pervasive intent of healing and harmony in them, as
well as the intent to be inspirators for luck, wellfare and wellbeing
in a general way, meditaiton, good sex, rejuvenation and everything...!)
In
any case, when
some harmony has been emphasized, when dance has
enlivened the muscles and enriched the mind with possibilities, the
issues of emotional bitterness, hatred and so on can be faced more
rapidly, with greater possibility of immediate and deep change. If it
seems impossible or just too sad to meet, it makes sense with some
affirmation or suggestive approaches, saying such things as
'gratefulness' repeatedly, meditating on such holistic-sounding words
as Ama (representing love or the female power) and Rama (representing
generosity in strength or the male power; these sounds are from my own
intuitive whispering. One can also say AmaRama and wait a minute in
silence before saying it again, about five times, as a general
cleansing, I find).
In
a summerly
feeling, one can then focus on the issues that lead to
pain or which feels related to bitterness and suffering, not with an
objective to pinpoint an enemy or do further pointless scape-goating
but to see the fallacy of engaging in any form of hatred whatsoever.
Then,
after a
suitable process of exploration -- perhaps also through
writing -- there will be a relief. It is not always necessary, perhaps
very rarely only, to actually write concretely about an emotional
problem. Rather, it is possible to write such things as one could
imagine that a wise person would say to oneself on hearing some
elements of the emotional problem, but not the concrete details.
To
get up from the
depths of emotional trouble it is important to
emphasize that an emotion may "grab" the self or the perspective of
life so that everything else seems small -- while it is in actuality so
that the emotion may be small and everything else vast -- and so the
Popper notion of "refutability" comes in here also. The emotions that
seem most absolute are those which are connected to tales which are
sustained "against reality", they are described in a way which seems
irrefutable, which considers reality and everything else but what is
after all a petty emotion insignificant.
The
grounds, then,
for a lot of the emotional turmoil that a sensitive
heart may feel characterises all of humankind, and has done so since
time immemorial, may be a reluctance in human thought to grant
subsistence to reality. These things can be suggested when one is in
harmony but to someone who is crying her hearts out it may seem remote.
To
be realistic
about the extent and depth of feeling, a little
emphasis on practical things, but no drugs, I would suggest, makes
sense. Avoiding drugs means that the emotion is not connected to
distorted brain waves which may be largely unaccessible except when in
a drugged state and hardly even then. Alcohol is a strong drug inducing
a lot of emotional changes, increases emotional vulnerability and a
tendency to be insensitive to synchronicities and spiritual realities.
It is no coincidence that the spiritual climate of the American Indians
declined with their introduction to alcohol by the europeans.
When
a release
from more concrete emotions have happened, it is urgent
not to stop there but to continue the quest for a more general
enlightenment or awakening in which the issue as a whole is understood
in a sustained flash of insight. In this sustained flash or light the
whole nature of thought blocking reality and putting its own reactions
and priorities up as higher and more important than those arising from
the ocean of goodness as whispers of love in one's heart is understood,
one goes for walks and writes reflectively and paints and feels it
over, feels whether it is possible to stay out of the turmoil of ego
altogether and for always.
This
enquiry will
be free only if one does not let oneself believe in
Tibetan masters, in Christian priests, in Zen masters, in Imam or Sufi
teachers, in Jewish Kabbalistic teachers, in Hindi Tantric teachers, in
Dao teachers, in Nietszche propagandists, and so on and so forth. One
must not think that a person who speaks with certitude about this and
who lets disciples crowd around him or her paint the central person in
glossy golden colors have any insight at all. There is no reason why
this person should not be at least as nutty as anyone else picked from
a crowd. If one goes on believing in reincarnated masters and their
organisations one will only project the real work on enlightenment to
some imagined future. One will then be stuck in a false process of
'becoming' instead of facing up to the potential and truth here and now.
When
one leaves
aside all thoughts of progress towards enlightenment by
some technique, method, teacher or scheme, then one comes down to the
truth of looking for enlightenment in a series of central insights
which all works to explode the ego. This is something which involves
the kind of grace that comes in understanding that which one doesn't
before understand in making a painting; it is like hitting on a new
melody, seeing something in a way which is unique to oneself and which
nevertheless is of such a general nature that one emerges a teacher.
Humanity
is a
big-brained and highly sexed race, requiring a culture of
enlightenment. To sustain such a culture we must be willing to dissolve
all aspects of our conditioning and cultures which are tainted with
violence against life, violence against ourselves, violence against
individuals, violence against our minds, violence against animals,
violence against trees and so on. We must step out of our mis-cultures
and nurture a new kind of culture in which essential all are teachers,
all are, in a sense, messiahs, preaching quietly, being artists,
showing what it means to have love as a sun to everyone else. If this
seems strange think of how the cells collaborate in a healthy body:
each is a light to the whole body, each takes a full responsibility, we
might say.
But
there is thing
about pleasure. If you have freedom, what's the
trouble about pleasure? Why not take pleasure in pleasure if you are
free? If you have seen the rejuvenating great truth of freedom from
attachment, can you then not enjoy icecream? Sex? Dance? Must you do
some stale kind of Astanga Yoga incessently and get as wrinkled as
those who do any stale kind of atheletic discipline instead of being a
winner in your own life, dancing and doing free yoga, free improvised
yoga, free improvised massage, free improvised sex, free improvised
reading and writing and exploration. How to avoid that these things
become a thing of the ego? Simple. Avoid it! Avoid it by avoiding it.
Avoid it by having the sustained insight in these things, keeping up
the sense of learning about enlightenment always, looking into the
nature of attachment -- not only in your own psyche, but in those which
you relate to, through your compassion.
Is
it ever said
enough about enlightenment? Obviously not. I call on
each individual who takes these themes seriously in his or her life to
build up new ways of expressing things in a free, refutable, open
society-friendly manner, to express the central themes of freedom from
tradition, enlightenment and so on and so forth without putting
themselves on a pidestall, implicitly or explicitly, without taking
disciples, without speaking out of immature reverence for this or that
individual but learning from K R Popper in being eclectic about what we
are exposed to, looking into each proposition with a calm head and a
warm heart, feeling over whether it holds or not... Do so, express a
teaching, keep on improvising it and don't make a system of it. For the
devil is in the system. I pray that nothing of what I do is a system,
not even the following proposals, which have a flavour of the systemic
perhaps, but which are still open. A language is open per se, per
definition, and this is an open-minded theory about the universe. Good
luck in your own explorations. This is the final chapter on questions
of awakening your feelings in this book manuscript.
*
Macroscopic
nonlocality
Let
us here look
at physics in a way which sometimes is gradual and explorative way and
at other times jumps straight to the heart (I hope) of issues which
have been discussed here and there for the past fifty years or so. As a
finale, we will give some illustrations of a formalisation in the form
of three computer programs, three 'manhattan' programs as I call them,
in an approach developed by myself in this context. The language
manhattan, or manhattan forth, is a version of Forth by Charles Moore
entirely adopted as a language of new physics as I have brought it on
here. You can start it in Green Cat, which is ordinarily provided as
CDROMs for PCs in this book as I sell it on my talks or exhibitions or
both. It is open source, and the Forth compiler is based on some open
source material from the Forth community, all included. The interaction
with the 3d and XML by Daeron Meyer in his JGV module, as also
included, is done by myself.
The first example,
supermodel1 is
automatically started (and suggested each time you click 'load a new
program'), when the option 'manhattan' is selected from the 2d or the
3d menu in Green Cat.
The underlying
research question is: How can quantum
mechanical theory and general relativity theory be
combined with a minimum loss of theoretical simplicity and no less at
all of numerical predictions, in fact, the opposite, with additional
new numerical predictions?
The chapter is written for spiritual people with a broad mind and sharp
logic with a great deal of knowledge about all areas of physics; it has
been rewritten many times and in the process some arguments are a bit
upside down and other issues are dealt with in a way which I see could
have been ten times clearer. Also, lots of repetative introductory
comments have been left intact before the meat of the theory is finally
revealed. However, with these short-comings, I still
feel it is 'doing the job' of providing a rational ground for a
spiritual trust in synchronicities, karma and good luck and such nice
things, on the basis of an openly changing four-dimensional (or
more-dimensional than that even) reality which is in some kind of
contact or resonance with the present moment. I find that it is not
necessary to go to hyperabstract mathematics to do this, as I have seen
some physicists have done it; rather it is possible to look at the
components of the main theories and bring them together in a way which
preserves the empirical predictions while modifying these components to
a new whole. It is not simple, this bringing together, because the
refinement and scope and variety of empirical predictions demands a
certain minimum simplicity (I think). However it has its simplicity as
one becomes familiar with the way of thinking involved (it is likely to
take some time).
The issue of whether quantum nonlocality can have biological relevance
is dealt with in a minimum way here, but adequate to say: it is clearly
a strong potential, even likelihood, if the basic proposals as outlined
here indeed are hitting the mark. For the interconnectedness of quantum
theory is, in this theory as here presented, called 'supermodel
theory', given a very general condition to arise, a condition involving
contrasting similarities and similar contrasts in a fluid and open
sense; and the step from such a general condition (which must be
tested, and indeed the theory leads to novel empirical predictions
which can be tested, and as such the theory is refutable) to a
biological relevance -- indeed, to a notion of 'macroscopic
nonlocality' -- is not nearly as tall as it used to be.
Macroscopic nonlocality of a kind which is subtle (rather than coarce
and intensive as in superconductivity) involves that the nonlocalities,
even though they play themselves out through extremely fine levels of
energies, are, by structural arrangements, 'amplified' so that higher
levels of energies are responsive to them; and also so that higher
level of energies can communicate to finer levels of energies. I leave
it to biologists to work this out; there are many ways in which one can
sketch such 'energy level amplification'. With the expanded type of
nonlocality prediction as found in supermodel theory, there will be a
motivation for such theorizing over biological nonlocality.
The theory itself will come out by reading this chapter forwards,
backwards, sidewards and not at all.
Let me however point out that the macroscopic and biological
nonlocality I suggest that exist is of a type which is not mechanical
or automatic but which requires extraordinary harmony along the lines
suggested in all the foregoing chapters. I do not agree with those
theorizers over the human mind which suggest that the mind is at all
times fully engaging in the nonlocal. Rather, the nonlocal is an
amazing potential, a fantastic option, a great and important and vital
possible realization. We can rationally think about this potential
through physics and its empirical findings, when we theorize over them
in such a way as this; however it would be immature to think that it
'explains consciousness' when consciousness is confused and rather
mechanical and in little need of any explanation. It is rather the
transformed consciousness it is about. Thus, my personal feeling of
importance about physics as seen in this chapter is to show that a
transformed consciousness, free from self or ego, with a grounding in a
real and actual and not illusory contact with a boundless
interconnectedness, is possible: it is not my presumption to declare
that it is realized. I say this strongly because I do not feel that
this point has been adequately discussed among a number of the rather
sloppy discussions of nonlocality by hopeful mysticists which have
reached the bookstores; and the lack of emphasis on refutability is
also noted in some of these rather monomanic works.
Let us characterize general relativity theory and quantum mechanical
theory (GRT and QMT) in extremely simple ways, not presuming absolute
completeness.
GRT offers a
picture of a possible reality. QMT offers no clear-cut
picture but a collection of postulates.
GRT
is simple,
however some postulates must be re-interpreted to a
"metaphorical" level unless we want to revolutionize QMT.
For
instance, GRT
involves the ideas that local correlations is
adequate to explain all correlations. QMT involves nonlocal
correlations.
We
can
metaphorically accept local correlations as an idea if we apply
it, not to the space-grid, but to the contents between the supermodels.
GRT
denies
absolute simultaniety. QMT as by Schroedinger uses absolute
time. In our theory, we can accept that there is no absolute
simultaniety at the space-grid (here called space-duration) level, but
consider that the constellation of supermodels have its own
higher-level duration (to avoid saying "absolute time").
The
nonlocal
correlations in QMT will offer no contradiction, then, as
regards simultaniety. FOr they will simply be interpreted as regarding
a higher-level duration than the GRT level.
GRT
involves, here
*
correlations in space-duration, so that the general
relativity holds
*
this correlation involves, as we have said earlier,
curvatures in space-duration
*
implying a similarity for different observers as to
generalized motion aspects
*
implying an equivalence of accelleration and gravitation
with each other and with curvature
*
curvature implying also a measurable slowing of duration
within a process
*
curvature spreading wavelike with the speed of light
* an
emphasis on different parts of space-duration being
manifest (for different observers), so there is no absolute
simultaniety at this level
*
there is a natural unfoldment indicated by the
organising factor of square of c (the square of the speed of light in
vacuum) (the square abstractly suggesting two dimensions are involved
somehow)
* but
(we say) light itself is considered to be a kind of
nonlocal connection between the discrete points in space-duration
Whereas
QMT
involves, here
*
correlations going beyond space-duration, or contact
points between supermodels (of which space-duration is merely one,
albeit a central and stable one), and this appears as "nonlocality" for
an observer in space-duration
*
these correlations are rather as "resonances", in that
they can be entrained by such situations as the EPR
* but
they can also be "discovered" without such initial
local entrainment as in the EPR by virtue of the principle of movement
towards wholeness
* an
uncertainty or complementarity involving such
observables as position and momentum
*
continuity at factorized high-energy situations being,
at closer inspection, a result of fine-grained quantized energy
situations in which energy is related to frequency times Planck's
constant in an indivisible sense
* in
fact, the entrainment of nonlocality by local contact
in the EPR situation can be considered a special case of the
"discovery" kind of nonlocality -- ie, it can be considered a special
case of an application of the principle of movement towards wholeness
or PMW
A
theoretical
simplicity is thus achieved by PMW. But this is also
leading to novel numerical predictions of a refutable kind, as required.
For
neither GRT
nor QMT allows a meaningful prediction of nonlocality
arising due to similarities and contrasts over distance in the
space-duration (and, indeed, anywhere in between the supermodels)
However,
we must be clear in our minds that there are important
differences between "our" GRT and, say, Einstein's GRT (such as we
having a discrete space-duration instead of a continous space-time),
and so also for QMT. Since there is a little more anarchy in the
current physics as regards QMT and its dozens of alternative
formulations and interpretations, it is less important to point out the
particular differences between "our" QMT and conventional QMT.
Furthermore,
I do
not feel it is a complexification of our theory of
supermodels to suggest that there may be more levels of yet subtler (or
more "super") kinds in which, say, a range of "constants" even smaller
than Planck's constant apply. So we will use an informal language which
is as free from the sense of absolutes as at all possible. The fact
that physics can progress should not lead us to be absurd reductionists
in the meantime.
One of the most
interesting concepts which emerged in the physics of
the twentieth century was that of nonlocality or alocality, which is to
say, some kind of immediate link or contact or connection or
interconnetedness not limited by the speed of light and not typically
causal. A form of direct relationship between anything and anything
even across time, a concept which Einstein offered a great deal of
noble resistance against and which only came to full light through
laboratory experiments in the 1980s (by Aspect and others following
up). So, at the moment of writing this (2004), physicists have not
still fully digested the implications of nonlocality, a concept which
breaks fundamentally with the forefather of early physics, Isaac Newton.
Is
nonlocality
only a special feature of some microscopic energy
events? Or is nonlocality also relevant at a macroscopic level,
including human beings? Nonlocality in conventional quantum physics is
predicted to occur only at extremely specialized conditions; some of
these may be macroscopic (like superconductors and supermagnets) but in
general, at ordinary temperatures and with, for instance, biological
material, it is not supposed to occur, generally speaking. Some
physicists, including David Bohm and Roger Penrose, have speculated as
to whether it might occur in a way which is directly relevant for the
human brain. But they have not found solid grounding in the physics of
the twentieth century for that claim. Several thinkers, interested in
parapsychology and the like, including Erwin Lazslo, have sought to
explain worldviews in which nonlocality plays a profound role; but this
has so far not been taken seriously by active physicists, generally
speaking, because -- quite simply -- there is no clear and obvious and
good way to bring it into the biological sphere when one starts with
something like Niels Bohr's work on quantum theory.
For
instance,
Niels Bohr formulated a 'principle of correspondence',
which was a heuristic tool (I would say) to build up early quantum
theory, and it goes rather like this: for energies far away, in orders
of degree, from the extremely minuscle size of Planck's constant,
quantum theory should not yield other numerical empirical predictions
than conventional classical mechanics as of Newton, Maxwell etc. Of
course, this correspondence principle must be regarded as an element of
a theory and as such we must ask whether it has been tested, whether it
can be tested, whether it has stood these tests -- in short, whether it
is refutable and has not been refuted but in fact to some extent been
confirmed. Alas, as a heuristic tool, it has not been considered in
this light (very much).
As
far as the
emergence of the concept of nonlocality goes, it has been
connected to extremely special initial conditions, such as in the
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen experiment (EPR for short); and even there it
is arising only indirectly and in a way in which it took several
decades to unravel the numerical implications of (through the work of J
S Bell and others).
In
the present
chapter, I will elaborate a very different theory than
quantum theory, which is having the numerical predictions of existing
quantum theory and also of general relativity theory as special cases
of itself. But this very different theory, utilzing a new concept --
that of the 'supermodel', a generalization of the concept of model --
and utilizing a new formal language, which I have created here and
which is called 'manhattan' -- is such that it predicts pervasive
nonlocality, also at a macroscopic level, in way which may plausibly
also be relevant for human beings and biological living substance in
general. So, there are additional (refutable) numerical predictions.
The
computer
simulation or visualisation through some formal
'illustrations' of the theory (the theory regarded as essentially
informal, in line with the thoughts presented earlier in this book) is
consciously simple and without glossy elaborations. The formal language
I have invented to give rise to an almost 'alphabetic' visulisation,
which does not conceal hard edges, does not throw in artificial things
such as 'texture files' or 'light sources' but which keep things so
that we can think about the relationship of the visual to the (formal)
text.
When
I now create
a new theory, the theory of supermodels, I do so
because I feel that macroscopic nonlocality is the most solid way to
perceive a rational ground for spirituality in a nonfundamentalistic
open way, suitable to give strength to our dialogue and our
explorations with a great sense of the possibilities of
interconnectedness in between all living beings and indeed also between
your own mental processes, including brain and neural processes, and
that of, potentially at least, everything else in the universe.
However, I do not claim that supermodel theory in any way 'proves' that
such spirituality does have a solid ground; merely that it is a way of
perceiving 'what is' in which it makes sense to explore the
possibilities of this.
I
wish to also
state that I profoundly disagree with an element of the
thinking of Roger Penrose and of Erwin Laszlo as regards the view of
the human mind: as I see it, the extraordinary interesting phenomena of
extra-sensory perception or ESP and the like, including psychokinesis,
is something which may be largely an illusion to a mind which is not
completely selfless, which has not completely transformed itself, gone
out of the sphere of desire, greed, hatred, and dogmatism. The fruitful
exploration of ESP and the like should, I feel, go together with an
exploration of the freeing of the mind of illusions. Otherwise, it may
be a mere expansions of the illusions of the ego, an expansion of the
gullible nature of the mind. A healthy, transformed, awakened state of
mind has extraordinary quantities of macroscopic nonlocality -- but the
human mind, when ravaged by the disappointments of broken attachmnts
and all that is not characterised by pervasive nonlocality. The human
mind does have a potential, though. It is the potential for a kind of
infinity and something going entirely beyond all local causation that
is important, as an encouragement, we might say, for spiritual free and
open exploration. The theory as here presented explains rationality why
we may have such a potential but it does not assert that we have
realized this potential nor that it is very easy to do so. As far the
biological realm goes, it is more a theoretical backdrop or worldview
than any concrete theory. A biological theory may be erected within it,
explaining, for instance, relationships between cell membranes or DNA
vibrations and macroscopic nonlocality as flows from a supermodel
theory; this is not something I have done here but it is logically a
possibility. In fact, there is a great deal of such logical
possibilities flowing from supermodel theory; so it should be of great
interest to a great deal of people to test supermodel theory and find
out whether it can fruitfully replace quantum theroy and also general
relativity theory as a foundation theory in physics, as I can think it
can, of course.
Again,
the
computer illustrations are crude and simple, so that we can
focus on the meaning of them, rather than considering them a kind of
'propaganda' for the theory. You are of course free to make additional
formal illustrations and explore the present ones in modified forms,
because, in this book, I supply the whole language, also on CDROMs, so
that it can be performed by mostly any computer (insofar as it has
well-documented video cards, suitable for early versions of GNU/Linux
such as Red Hat 8.0).
What I have here
is
something submitted in the sense of popperian refutability for anyone
to explore in a true scientific spirit, in freedom from dogma and
tradition, with a both sharp and open mind, not gullible, not taken to
superstition or callous sceptisism. The sceptic, by the nature of the
greek verbal root of the word, is one who looks around, wondering; this
is what the sceptic Arne Naess has told me, and he is one of the
persons who gave me advise on some of the more general issues involved
in this investigation; so has David Bohm, and indeed I concur to some
of his descriptions of physical processes but not to all of them; other
acknowlegments elsewhere in this book.
I
regard the
supermodel theory as presented in an as complete form as
it should be presented, generally speaking, in this book; and I will
occasionally elaborate on features in the informal talks I am giving,
regularly, in various continents etc, but do not think I will give more
written descriptions of the theory nor develop the manhattan language
formalism further. As I say also elsewhere in this book, I feel the
foundation is adequate as an open, non-fundamentalistic, explorative,
dialogic work in which each individual can make his or her own fruitful
good contributions and in which an infinity of insights can come, so
that we can come into a state of mind which is not merely thoughtful,
but insightful, and through that insightfulness, also awakened, aware,
and with a great deal of the energy of attention at all levels, leading
to luck and good synchronicities in all areas of living. This is my
intent, and the spiritual sense of openness as exemplified in the
refutability quality as indicated by Karl R Popper is in coherence with
this intent, and more so than in coherence with the boring theory of
science as propagandized by Niels Bohr and his disciples. One of his
disciples, Kristoffer Gjoetterud, a physicist at the University of
Oslo, was proundly against all such attempts as by David Bohm to think
afresh the perspectives of Niels Bohr. Many physicists have regarded
themselves as some kind of priests for a given gospel; their profession
and perhaps international prestige among other physicist/priests made
them into a most powerful group, exemplifying the exact opposite of
refutability. The meeting with such fundamentalistic
non-refutability-oriented, 'closed society'-oriented pseudo-scientists,
in several countries, made me realize that just as spirituality is not
best entertained by socalled 'spiritual organisations' so is science
not best entertained by socalled 'scientific organisations'.
A
scientist, then,
is one who stands alone, against all group pressure,
in freedom from seeking rewards and points of prestige from the
intercultural sects of science, who emphases refutability in an open
sense in as many parts of his or her work as possible, in respect for
the greatness of the world beyond human thought. A scientist is one who
actively fights his or her prejudices as well as superstitions, and who
look for such thoughts as can be said to have a sense of affinity with
reality, though with a fair amount of uncertainty in them -- a person
who looks for fact whether he or she likes them or not. Such persons
may not exist in any of the most prestigious scientific institutions.
However, these institutions may contain a fair amount of fairly
objective recording of empirical results. By looking at them, in
theoretical openness, in the freedom to theorize again -- knowing that
each set of data is compatible with an infinity of theories -- an
individual human being, a scientist by intent and by personal practise,
if not also by education -- can transcend the folly of all
institutions. He or she will find in Albert Einstein's work sentiments
shared with what I just said, even though Einstein at several points
were stubborn and appeared closed-minded. However, Niels Bohr and his
coercion must be regarded as uncalled for. Much of the cold, callous,
cunning materialism which has flooded into science as a whole from
physics came from the coldness and crudeness of the vague formulations
of Bohr with his Copenhagen Interpretation; in commenting on the role
of a work by a good-hearted scientist like David Bohm, Bohr wrote: it
may be that, under certain circumstances, two plus two equals five.
This is the type of sarcasm that drives and is the motor of the worst
in science. As a scandinavian-born person, I challenge the paradigm of
Niels Bohr and call for a total re-evaluation of the role of
nonlocality in all of science, starting with physics, through the
theory of supermodels as I here present for the first time. I call for
a realization of what David Bohm and F David Peat wrote in their book,
"Science, order and creativity": that the existence of 'paradigms' in
science is indication of confusion and that good science is absolutely
free from all sorts of paradigms and also from series of paradigms.
Paradigm is a misuse of power. Science is about refuting misuse of
power, refuting illusions, refuting superstitions, refuting
over-sceptical thoughts, refuting shallowness, and creating the open
mind characterised by attentiveness and willingness to challenge each
and every thought. Science, through refutability, is spiritual and has
nothing whatsoever to do with the mastery of a technique, a vocubulary
or with the inculcations into the ways and rites of a cult or clan
deeming itself 'scientific'. I call for a dissolution of the
institutions and for a new generosity among thinking people to share
their thoughts in a refutable way, hiding their titles and titulations
if they have any. I don't have any titles to hide, fortunately...
*
So,
here I bridge
some components of an essential nature from the two
main branches of modern physics, general relativity theory and quantum
theory; the former being primarely the work of Albert Einstein and the
latter the work of a group of people not excluding Einstein but in
which people like Niels Bohr, Louis de Broglie, Heisenberg,
Schroedinger, Dirac and others have been dominant. There have been
attempts, of only limited success earlier, to bridge these two main
branches. The approach taken in the most-published version of these
attempts has been heavily mathematical (superstring and M-theory). The
approach taken by the forefathers of modern physics was not primarely
mathematical; nor is this attempt primarely mathematical. Indeed, the
chapter in which an exploration of infinity took place earlier in this
book has led this author to a greater caution than ever as to the
belief in a concept of socalled 'pure' mathematics which is, as if,
devoid of essential uncertainty. Rather, mathematics is by this author
seen as merely a bunch of heuristic tools and nothing of a foundational
nature as far as making a theory goes. In this way, the present theory
as here presented, of what I call 'supermodels', is in essence an
informal theory and the role of the formal language here invented,
which also enables computers to show the visualization incorporated in
the theory, is only to illustrate a few abstract components of the
theory. The theory is by nature informal and the formal language is
considered here to be an exemplification of some elements of the
theory, while it is the informal exposition of the theory, beyond any
such concept as 'axiom' or 'deduction', which is considered the essence
of the theory.
As
theory, it is
very different from quantum theory (which Einstein, by
the way, did not feel was a full-fledged theory in a real sense) and
also from general relativity theory. However, the numerical predictions
are identical for all tested areas. In addition, a component of
refutability is invoked because some novel numerical predictions come
out of supermodel theory.
Supermodel
theory
involves a discussion of a lot of rather complex
reports from laboratories, as generalized through the formal structures
involved in GRT (general relativity theory) and QT (quantum theory). It
is therefore not simple for one who is not fully acquinted with all
these reports. However, given the complexity of the essential processes
of universe as suggested by these reports, it is a fairly simple way of
summarizing them. A great advantage over GRT and QT is that the present
theory can be fully described without reference to any specialised area
of mathematical tool-making. The suggestions in GRT as to curvature etc
are taken seriously but some suggestions or propositions in GRT are
taken only in a metaphorical sense; much the same can be said of
suggestions or propositions in QT. As theory, the theory is not
containing GRT nor QT as special cases; as for its empirical numerical
predictions, the empirical numerical predictions of GRT and QT are
special cases (this discernment I have derived from a conversation with
Arne Naess on the relationship between Newton's classical mechanics and
Einstein's relativity mechanics).
The
way I present
it, I rely on the subtle mind of the reader to
apprehend the fullness of the theory as a way of perceiving the world,
and I do not make it too simple to derive numerical predictions from
it. For my feeling underlaying this work is that it can aid the sense
in which macroscopic nonlocality across both distances in space and
distances in duration can play an active role at all levels in creation
-- also for human beings, also as synchronicity, also in a spiritual
sense. So my intent is spiritual not technical nor oriented towards
satisfying the compulsion among some physicists for yet more equations
and the like.
The
prerequisite
for reading this chapter is everything essential about
modern physics, computer science and 3d modelling, with an emphasis on
the disagreements between the forefathers of quantum theory (and with
Einstein); updated with recent works in the wake of J. S. Bell's
careful destruction of portions of John von Neumann's 'proof' that
hidden variable-theories does not work; and with a refreshing amount of
talent to challenge existing ways of doing things along the lines
suggested by all the earlier chapters of this book. What can come out
of this, for the intent enquirer, is a rational grounding in an
undogmatic sense of spiritual faith involving synchronicities,
intuition about a future that is in open dialogic change and so on.
There are elements here which those who engage in experimental physics
of the quantum kind can work on so as to check the theory. Ie, it is
refutable. It is one of the first fairly simple bridges between the
numerical predictions of quantum theory and the numerical predictions
general relativity theory which are also realistically refutable, and
which carries its own formal language to illustrate parts of the
theory. The theory in itself is regarded as a work of thought, because
the view that the essence of a theory lies in equations is not at all
shared in this book.
I
would say,
therefore, that it is inadequate and not even necessary to
have a standard education in the current idea of physics as taught at
universities to make good sense of the present chapter. One needs a
different kind of background, which is best acquired not through exams
and laboratories but by being willing to expand one's vocabulary both
philosophically, physically, in terms of computer science and in terms
of life as a whole, while exploring what may be a sense of undivided
wholeness of all life at the same time; looking for coherence, having
an intent of a unified vision in which nothing is explained 'away', a
vision which is open to the dialogic feeling of all life and nature, a
vision which allows the universe to be bursting of life and
intelligence and which does not attempt to 'reduce' or 'oversimplify',
and which nevertheless clearly and succinctly lays out why both the
numerical predictions of quantum theory, by and large, and the
numerical predictions of general relativity theory, by and large, make
an awful lot of sense.
We
give absolutely
no credence to the prestige of a theory here; we
consider everything refutable in a popperian sense, and look only to
its numerical predictions and to the extent it has been checked; and
then we ask: what might be natural ways to give ideational forms so as
to incorporate a sense of the full patterns of these predictions? And
that is indeed what it is to create theorein -- a spectre or view of
phenomena, of a reality or an actuality beyond our thoughts. In this,
there is no a priori reason to give any credence at all to mathematics
of any kind. Indeed, we must be wary of all rule-based schemas because
the universe which we approach may well be both infinite and flexible
in the sense: entirely beyond all rules. It follows from an earlier
chapter, in which we look into the nature of numbers and collection of
numbers when we 'go to infinity', that we must be extremely cautious
about applying any concept of socalled 'pure mathematics' -- for all
mathematics is 'dirty' with perception and uncertainty, we might say.
In other words, mathematics is just a bunch of rules, a bag of tricks,
and when we seek, as physicists, or as philosophers, to think about the
whole of existence and not just a part of it, then we must not treat a
bag of tricks -- ie, heuristics -- as something static or permanent or
solid.
Rather,
we must
describe the perception process. In making a formal
language, we are making what we may imagine to be a clearer theory but
in fact we are merely illustrating the theory. A formal language can
never capture the richness of an informal discussion. An education in
socalled 'natural sciences' which does not give 90% focus on informal
descriptions has lost its essence and has degenerated to a mere issue
of being talented at skills in 'dealing' with issues in reality rather
than perceiving them. Here, we challenge the whole idea that physics
can be a profession and that physics has anything to do with what is
taught as a profession, and regard the sentiments of Popper as
indicative of a love of reality that is willing to challenge all
priesthoods of science.
The
chapter is
written for individuals who seek a grounding of a
holistic understanding so as to comprehend the vast technical
developments which has come out of quantum theory and also the
relativity theories, a holistic understanding which is entirely free
from superstitions related to astrology and alchemy and such, and which
is both undogmatic and infinitely aware of the immensity of the
developments in modern science as to the study of reality; but who are
unsatisfied with the fragmented approach both of the Copenhagen
Interpretation, the general relativity-priests, superstring/ M-theory
etc, and who wants a radical rethinking of the whole in a way which
makes utterly sense.
To
me, this makes
sense. It may do so for you, as well. I offer this
not as a contribution to practical physics because practical physics
has a tendency to become bombs and I want to offer that no support at
all; I do not support the idea of military-budget physicist work, nor
do I support the idea that the leaders of a fragmented paradigm should
perpetuate their stale systems of thought by giving prices, such as
Nobel price, to each other -- this is but a soldifying of an elite
which should never have been an elite in the first place. A
refutability-friendly individual does not give a price but rather
engages in dialogue. Physics, by and large, is an entirely corrupt
profession which is uninterested in reality and basically interested in
supporting its own fragmented existence. However, the field is unique
in that, among its archived and acknowledged content, there is
something that no priesthood can deny, that nobody can reasonably claim
is all a hoax, and that is open for everybody to think about: the
numerical data from decades of studies by individual people in
different continents of microscopic and macroscopic events, studied by
means of relatively neutral forms of technology such as electron
microscopes and telescopes.
It
is a careful
study of the numerical predictions without bothering to
pay too much attention to the historical quarrels over them, in terms
of which theoretical paradigm that should 'win', which gives something
fresh, unique, and historical important. Anyone who in any sense
supports a paradigm or even a series of paradigms is intrinstically a
fascistoid person, not interested in reality but only in setting a
standard, a vision, so as to ensure his or her own power. A paradigm is
exactly what science is not about, what philosophy is not about -- a
paradigm is a power structure and a series of paradigms is like a
series of bloody revolutions; it is not that which thinking nor love
nor affection nor enlightenment is about.
In
this spirit, I
set forth what may be a well-working theory of the
universe in which both gravitation and nonlocality is encountered for,
so that nonlocality also plays a role in biological phenomena and also
at the human scale. I believe that this may be the first time such a
programme has been carried out to the extent it has been carried out in
this book. This is not to attempt to create a new paradigm at all.
Rather, it is done in the spirit of suggesting ways in which reality
actually may be in itself, apart from any model of it. These open
suggestions involve refutability. They are, in other words, postulated
facts.
What
is a fact? A
fact is a thought, of course, but also more than just
any thought: it is a thought which has many points of contact with
something beyond thought -- actuality, reality, 'what is' -- and these
points of contact are so that there is an element of harmonious
synchronicity or matching of patterns of contrasts and similarities in
them. Ie, the patterns of the thought is in some kind of open
correspondence, coherence and affinity at many points with something
which it refers to; and it is so that it aids perception in an unbiased
way. From a mysticist point of view, a thought used by silence is (or
may be) a fact.
The
present
theory, as offered, does not succumb to any dogma that
physics or a theory of the universe or the world or whatever one calls
the manifest level of existence as it appears to us human beings 'must'
be based on a notion of 'energy' nor of 'time' nor of 'space'. It
rather begins on the notion that it is possible to make some sense of a
great deal of the abstract patterns of the reported numerical
experiments and that we can, with a suitable sense of refinement in our
minds, and a dialogic, explorative attitude, be able to extract what is
data so as to throw away theoretical garbage.
*
I
think that most
physicists who are in the process of thinking about
physics and not just 'doing' it, and who has an understanding both of
J. S. Bell's inequality theorem and of the empirical studies of it and
the EPR experiment, by the work of Aspect and others in 1980 and so
forth, would agree that if all this work had been done -- by some wierd
magic -- before 1915 or so, then the discussions about the foundations
of physics between Niels Bohr and Albert Einstein and between Niels
Bohr and other people in his group, including Erwin Schroedinger and
Louis de Broglie, and between these well-known physicists and other,
less well-known but influential physicists in their own way, such as
David Bohm, would have taken radically different turns on many crucial
points.
It
may be that
physics would have taken a turn as described in this
chapter, if by some yet more wierd magic computer language formalisms
were available at the time.
Indeed,
my
starting-point is something like the EPR experiment; we will
see the theory as unfolded, as described as a combination of suitable
elements of quantum theory and Einstein's general relativity theory,
both modified, illustrated by means of a formal description of three
situations:
*
An EPR-like
situation
*
An EPR-like
situation with gravitation (doing simply what M-theory is
doing in an overly complex way)
*
An EPR-like
situation in which the initial conditions have been
changed, yielding a new empirical prediction which can be regarded as
regarding the physics theory as here presented, which I call 'the
theory of supermodels', as refutable
The
third
situation involves, in other words, a clear-cut,
realistically checkable empirical prediction which flows from the
theoretical premises as here outlined. The initial condition will have
been altered so that the idea of the sole principle used in supermodel
theory, the principle of a tendency of movement towards wholeness, is
more explicitly seen to be operating. In fact, it was used in all three
examples; but the implications of using it is that a great deal more
nonlocality can be predicted to exist in reality, and this is a
refutable point, of course. With freedom from dependency of local
contact for nonlocal relationships to arise, we sketch a worldview in
which nonlocality is pervasive. This pervasiveness is such that we
would naturally expect macroscopic nonlocality to be a factor in cases
where the macroscopic structure is sensitive toward smaller and smaller
energy structures within itself. Such sensitivity can be thought of as
a kind of amplification of subtle fluctuations, rather as a radio
amplifies the electric fluctuations in its antennae; we might surmise
that the brain structure and the body in general, of human beings and
other animals, is like this. However, only in the context of a unified
theory in which nonlocality is accounted for in a pervasive way can
biologists look for nonlocality in a theoretically clarified way, with
regard to physics.
It
will be noticed
that there is no dependency on earlier forms of
mathematics; however the treatment will be very abstract, and indeed
the treatment of the EPR-like situation is on a purposedly nonconcrete
level. It flows from an intuition about physics, derived also from many
many summers of having conversations with active physicists over these
matters (see acknowledgements in the beginning of this book for the
most influential of these conversations), from attempting a number of
computer modellings of these, and from an attempt to reconcile
intuitions on the dynamism of duration and time in daily life with
these fundamental musings and possibilities beyond all dogma in
physics. I am definitely an outsider to the field and I am definitely
positive that by means of applying the popperian approach to science,
any outsider to any field of human thought can make a worthwhile
contribution. This is the result of many revisions indeed and I feel
that this has found a form which is adequate to account for the whole
of the essential physics of the twentieth century in a new key; the
language as here unfolded, the manhattan language, is proposed as a
native language of physics, and provided here in terms of both
documentation and full open source code in Java 1.1.8 and with the
three example programs or formal models, in Green
Cat, which is included on the CDROMs inside this book.
This
somewhat
large
chapter, beginning with informal explorations of the
present state of physics, continuing with elaborating a new concept of
what I call 'supermodels' (to distinguish them from the concept
'models', to which they have a few similarities, though), and finishing
with three such models in a new formalism, a tiny but excellent little
programming language made for the purpose and included on the CDROMs
with full source code make up what I feel is an adequate, however open,
theory of the
universe.
I
am sceptical,
though, with regard to a number of the preposterous,
presumptions, grandiose claims made by a number of the most socalled
'prominent' scientists of this day. We regularly hear of calculations
of the 'age', socalled, of the universe, as if it were a matter of some
adjustments of some figures. We regularly hear of socalled 'fundamental
forces'. We regularly hear of socalled 'fundamental building-blocks' of
the universe. And, indeed, we regularly hear of theories of everything
which do not have any of the most essential criterions fulfilled for
what it means to be a scientific theory. Speculations of a very free
kind, hypothesis of an ad hoc kind, are not science even though
prominent scientists agree about them! Science has nothing whatsoever
to do with agreement. Agreement may be collusion. The science that I
talk of is that which has, in each statement, a feeling of the insight
which can also have the quality of the refutable.
I
think that most
things said by socalled 'astronomers' and socalled
'physicists' about the universe is completely off the track. They
constitute something like a church and when the priests and popes of
this church speak, the newspapers quote them with rediculous reverence.
We know hardly anything about the universe which we inhabit. The sole
physicist of prominence, in recent times, who have said anything of
this nature, is David Bohm: there is infinitely much about matter which
physicists don't know, he said. Einstein, whose views of the universe
were rather much at odd with Bohm's, said, in a similar vein, as far
the theory of scienc goes: a theory which is not uncertain is not
a scientific theory. On the Copenhagen Interpretation he said: I do not
find that the empirical findings of the quantum type can justify a
change of the 'theory of science' itself. And when we talk of
uncertainty in a theory, we do not at all mean the socalled
'uncertainty principle', which is postulated with idiotic certainty.
The uncertainty principle should be called the uncertainty relation or
indeterminacy relation and it is a theory, or a component of a theory,
and this relation is of course not excempt from refutability. However,
since it does seems to say something essential, it means that it may
not easily get refuted; that is not to say that it is by itself some
kind of exception from the overall theory of science which we can
legitimately apply to all that we do with regard to the understanding
of the universe as a whole or in its particular: any postulate is a
theory, any theory is uncertain, and so also a theory about
uncertainty.
Niels
Bohr was a
meddled, confused thinker, overly concerned with
bridging people's independent approach into a kind of political group
which could oppose the paradigm set by Einstein. Niels Bohr tampered
with the theory of science is postulating a principle of
complementarity as something other than a refutable component. He
tampered with the theory of science in asserting that we should not try
to further analyse what goes on between measurements. He tampered with
the theory of science in putting forth the socalled 'correspondence
principle'. The fact that he was a genius, on occasion, in able to
describe features of the atom which baffled even Einstein does not mean
that Bohr was a genius all over; at most points his writings win only
because they are vague, imprecise, and hopelessly without the clarity
that we must require of a refutable theory. The paradigm set by Bohr
must be challenged just as much as the paradigm set by Einstein or
anyone else; science in essence is about a love for reality that makes
one speak clearly and undogmatically in a way which has refutability
all over. Much bad science came out of Bohr's work and some bad science
came out of Einstein's work. We should not wait a thousand years to
admit that; just as Karl Popper pointed out that we should not have
been so rediculously reverent to Aristotle and Platon when it is clear
that both philosophers were backward in their ethics as regarded
individual human beings, such as those called 'slaves', and when the
latter was clearly in favor of dictatorship. It is reverence for
fanatical and idiotic productions of thought that makes people get
killed; we must challenge all false reverence. Bohr was a powerful
manipulator of other scientists, as is clear for anyone who carefully
reads the stories of how he coerced various people, including Louis de
Broglie. Bohr was a politician more than an honest scientist, but he
had streaks of genius which makes it hard to separate the golden bits
from the many rotten pieces he shot into the core of science.
I
do not mean to
say that Popper got everything right either.
The
young Popper
was foolish enough to attack Heisenberg's uncertainty
principle in a way in which he exposed his lack of understanding of
nonlocality: Einstein put him right in a letter which Popper, humble to
fact, reproduced in later versions of his early work, The Logic of
Scientific Discoveries. I do not much like his early work, I lack in it
the subtle, ethically oriented, holistically careful mind of the wary
Popper in his two-volume production which I have spoken much of in this
book and will now set to work in my own theory in physics.
Having
challenged
the authorities in a way that I deem honest and
proper, honest to my own perception after a great deal of careful
enquiry over a long long time, honest also to my feeling that the
present account is fairly unbiased -- even unbiased by my friendship
with David Bohm -- I will now proceed to elaborating the theory slowly
and without making it easy for those who wish to make a system of it.
For it is no system. It is a living perception and it takes place in me
even as I write these sentences; it cannot be summed up as folly
'axioms'; it has no main equation, of course. It is idiotic to see to
extract that which cannot be extracted. Rather, it is a fullness of
coherent relationships between expressions, thoughts, feelings and
actuality as a whole, penetrated by refutability.
I
abhor the idea
of a system. A theory of a living universe cannot
possibly, to my mind, be a system. So I do not approve of the notion of
making a scheme of a theory. Please do not summarize the theory by
means of a scheme, if you wish to summarize the theory; rather give
your own fresh understanding and then acknowledge your direct source so
that people can look there for themselves. To put it in another way: if
you summarize it, it is a lie.
As
I said, this
theory is brought out in an explorative manner, gradually unfolding the
concepts and main issues more and more. (I deem that proper as regards
an unfinished universe ;)
*
The
concept of the
"supermodel", as here introduced, has the same
relationship to a text as an equation has to a number, generally
speaking. Unlike models, supermodels (now not speaking of fashion) are
self-active and recognisant of other models, and so create reality by
their interactivity. It is more active than the notion of a 'model',
has more features of some kind of inward level of sensitive subtlety
and so on, and may even be considered to be essentially infinite; and
indeed have some feature of consciousness of feeling. That is, it is a
nonreductive concept in which mind is in some open sense given a
priority to that of matter.
So
we see that
whereas the open concept of a 'model' has a role in
science, for scientists, so as to help perception; the concept of a
'supermodel' is rather more like the notion of 'correlation field'
which I postulated some summers ago in the little book, 'Sex,
meditation and physics' (though it is somewhat enhanced and refined
here). Supermodel is a self-active perception-like structural event
which relates to other supermodels and through them possibly, in a
self-referential way, also to itself; with features such as frequency
and the like, however reinterpreted without a prior designation of
space, time and energy. A supermodel is 'super' to models in that it is
self-active, it is somehow perceptual or involving a pattern
recognition of similarities and contrasts and indeed also a pattern
enforcer. It it is having an independent existence of the minds of
human beings.
We
will entertain
this concept, and look at the larger abstract
patterns of numerical predictions of quantum theory and general
relativity theory (which is by and large two divided schemas in
conventional modern physics), and gradually emerge the theory as a
whole, illustrating it by means of three formal examples, the EPR-like
situation, the EPR-like situation expanded rather effortlessly with
curvature to show the power of the wholeness of the theory, and the
EPR-like situation altered into a novel situation with novel empirical
predictions which can be checked by experimentative physics. If these
predictions do not hold, then the theory will be dust and ashes.
One
of the
characteristics particular to supermodels is shared with the
idea of a computer program (but not the other characteristics, at least
not in full). This is the characteristic which we may call 'behaviour'.
Another characteristic, which we may call 'flexibility', is not shared
with computer program texts, generally speaking.
Behaviour
involves
the capacity of a supermodel to incorporate a
stimulus (which we may call its 'female' aspect) and to emit a response
(which we may call the 'male' aspect, thinking of sexuality).
Evidently
one can
also speak of the behaviour of a computer program.
Flexibility
may be
emulated by a computer but not fully realized in a
digital context.
Flexibility
may
also be said to be a qualifying characteristic of the
behaviour characteristic, for it says: given a stimulus (if any) it is
no way to be sure (ie, absolutely certain) what, if any, the response
might be.
Flexibility
leads
one to speak of tendencies, though the tendencies may
be stable in some cases as seen from the perspective of, say, a human
being in an airplane. The construction of the airplane depends on
stability of such things as the relationship of mass to aerodynamic
lift; it would be absurd to insist -- on a practical level, that is --
that such things fundamental to its design are mere tendencies.
However, it is strictly true if the supermodel theory is held to be
valid, as we shall see.
Arne
Naess, in
several conversations we had on the nature of causality,
emphasized to me that he considered the concept of 'emergence' to be
fundamental. He explained it thus: in daily life, just as much as we
apply notions of cause and effects, we nevertheless grant that even if
all the causal conditions are present for something, say X, may happen,
it may be that something else emerges. This, he emphasized, can be
argued to be a worthwhile concept also at a level where we discuss a
theory of the essence of causality.
Flexibility
is a
vehicle for something operating in or on the
supermodels, and which in a sense is involved in their very nature and
certainly in their process of coming into being, and that is a
principle of a movement towards wholeness.
This
movement
operates through the flexibility aspect of the
supermodels. However, the flexibility aspect is not -- or at
least cannot be asserted with certainty to be -- only a vehicle for the
principle of movement towards wholeness. In addition, it may simply be
a flexibility -- as "for its own sake". Ie, it may be a sheer openness
in reality, or we cannot exclude this possibility.
The
principle of
movement towards wholeness is best seen indirectly
rather than directly. Ie, it is best seen when it has exerted itself
rather than by trying to cause it to exert itself. Of course, this is a
necessary by-product of associating it with a feature of flexibility
which is in itself indeterminate. It is not a law, strictly speaking.
The
principle of
movement towards wholeness suggests that when similar
contrasts and contrasting similarities (of order, pattern, process or
dance etc) can be radically enhanced in their degrees by a slight turn
(or change of some kind) then the turn is likely to occur.
This,
then, is an
art rather than a technique if transferred to the
human real of action (because of the infinity of both premises and
effects).
When
we want to
formulate a theory of the universe based on this
concept in the present context we would like two characteristics to be
fulfilled (at least): (1) relationship to presently acknowledged,
well-studied facts (or even some of the ideas involved in theorizing
over their summaries, such as 'curvature in four dimensions' to account
for 'gravity'), and (2) refutability in the sense of novel contact
points with reality, in a popperian sense.
(Naess
would
emphasize that a theory is relatively remote from empirics
in the sense that many steps of additional assumptions are usually
required to 'go' from a theory to something like a laboratory study and
'back', and so one cannot easily speak of falsification of a theory but
merely 'instances of disconfirmation' or 'instances of confirmation'.
However while this is probably an accurate description of how it often
is, I would suggest that the concept of refutability (more than the
earlier concept of falsification) is a quality which can pervade in
principle all of how we formulate and think of and feel about a theory,
and that this is a worthwhile and realistic goal. Whether there are
many or few contact points with laboratory studies and whether an
instance of disconfirmation amounts to something like a refutation is
in each case a matter of intuitive evaluation and dialogue.)
*
You
may have
heard of the distinction between an 'algorithm' and
'heuristics' in computer science and related areas. An algorithm is a
route procedure, a bound fixed set of rules so as to yield something
based on something else in a deteriminate manner.
In
contrast,
heuristics is a more open set of rather suggestive rules
or approaches which are not garanteed to work. In a sense, they have
something of the feature of a scientific proposition that Popper calls
'refutable', ie, they may work or not work.
Heuristics,
then,
is something like an algorithm but with a component
rather in tune with the flexibility that we introduced for the concept
of a supermodel.
When
we take this
as a foundational concept of a universe theory in
physics we see that indeterminism comes in through a flexibility that
look a little bit like heuristics.
A
physicist would
naturally ask: where in this approach do we find
something like an einsteinian spacetime?
From
this point
on, I regard the hundreds of volumes on classical and
modern physics as of the twentieth century to be the acknowledged
background for our discussion; these include a multitude of reports of
laboratory experiments and these experiments are considered primary to
the theoretical musings around these, for we are not dogmatists, are we?
The
answer to the
question in the former paragraph is that a spacetime
is an order which may perfectly well be represented by a single, though
exceptionally large, supermodel, of an exceptionally stable kind as far
as its overall structure goes, but with a natural ingredient of
curvature.
The
curvature
comes into the supermodel called spacetime by means of
certain easily changable elements within that supermodel.
Other
supermodels
relates to this supermodel so as to furnish it with
content and also receive information as to energies or masses. Remember
that a 'supermodel' is active in a subtle way, and that its activity
may relate to other supermodels. Since we are giving a vision of the
universe in a unified sense, we are proposing that supermodels make up
'what is', in some rather nonreductive sense. Yet since we have
purposedly brought in vague features of supermodels, such as infinity
and flexibility, this is not a systematic theory of the universe nor is
it a clearly reductive one and it is certainly not deterministic. The
word 'vision' is not entirely irrelevant and indeed something of the
essence of the idea of a theory involves just that. The view of a
theory in this regard is shared with Einstein more than those of 'the
Copenhagen Interpretation'.
As
for dimensions,
let us appreciate that when an architect constructs
a house then she or he must generally work with three dimensions, of
depth, height and width, but that the actual construction of the house,
physically, involves a fourth element, the duration of the construction
process, which can be imagined to be a kind of fourth dimension. (I
referred to the notion of duration also in the introduction and
mentioned there that Henri Bergson did important work on this concept;
he is one of the few in the history of well-known philosophy in Europe
who has done so, and in that regards he builds on Heraclit more than on
the fascistoid and pseudo-dialogical thinking of Platon or Hegel;
however the emphasis on the permanence of movement is found in many
non-European philosophies, including that of the Dao and of the Gunas;
I am grateful for discussions with Nicholas Hagger and Henrik B
Tschudi, several times, over these issues).
I
wish to qualify
the metaphysics involved here, in the concept
'spacetime'. The idea of four-dimensional space in which some kind of
process or duration is attributed to the fourth dimension is, also to
me, elegant, highly interesting, and most plausible.
So
I would
suggest, in an era more welcoming to indeterminism (phrased
as a negation) or an open future (phrase as an affirmation) that the
four-dimensional space in question is not to be called spacetime or
time-space but rather something else.
Let
me make this a
little more precise. Many elements of Einstein's
work involve a references to duration or process events so as to look a
little ahead or a little back with regard to any one process. However,
due to the idea of relativity, there is a particular form of openness,
so that there is no preferred point of reference. Part of the elegance
and overall simplicity of Einstein's work is that it is asserted that
all reference frames are in some sense equal.
The
notion of
relativity did not originate with Einstein but he was the
first to carry it out seriously as a foundational concept in a great
deal of physics, and not just for some phenomena.
So
it seems that
some reality of some sort should be attributed to
something more than merely the manifest present or manifest moment for
an 'observer' or for a reference frame.
However,
the type
of entanglement of probability densities found in
quantum experiments suggest that whatever the future of a process may
be, it is perhaps rather open in some ways, although there are
tendencies for it to be in this or that way.
Einstein
suggested
that this openness was an indication that physics
lacks certain developments and in principle it seems that he could be
right although at least the present prevailing intuition (and
consciously applied assumption) among many physicistists schooled in
quantum physics is that there is at least some genuine fluctuation
involved in the formation of what is to come.
I
have
encapsulated this openness by suggesting the essential role of
flexibility in supermodels.
However,
I think
it is wise to keep an open mind as to what extent this
freedom of fluctuation may be found to have more subtle patterns in the
future, Heisenberg's uncertainty principle proposal notwithstanding.
For
while
Heisenberg has proposed, with Bohr, that there are certain
complementary attributes in reality of which a further anylysis is
impossible, and in particular pointing to position - momentum
experiments such as in the double slit situation.
What
is the case,
however, is that the Copenhagen Interpretation,
socalled, of quantum theory, involves certain sentiments which does not
invite the idea of falsifiability or refutability on all points of
their physics, only on some.
So
it seems
adequate to say that only some parts of the Copenhagen
Interpretation are scientific. The rest must be regarded as a theory of
science or a metaphysics of a non-refutable kind and we must be at
liberty to discard it exactly because it is non-refutable (rather like
Freud's theories of mind). And
so we can see
here that part of Einstein's reaction against the
approach of Bohr was not merely as to his physics but as the
metaphysics and/or theory of science that Bohr sought to lay as a
foundation for physics.
The
many
universities and academic institutions that have since adopted
a simplified and technified version of the Copenhagen Interpretation
have then contributed to a situation in which we have a nonscientific
physics in part. We see that the institutions calling themselves
scientific in this sense are in need of a revision of their
foundational practise if Karl R Popper had it right, as far as I can
see.
The
approach I
would suggest is that a reformulation in as explicit
terms as possible of all assumptions and proposals involved in all
present foundational physics are put forward, so as to be able to
change the thought-content of these toward the type of statements that
have components of the refutable quality, or the scientific quality, in
them; and then, having changed thoughts, new formulations can be made.
I offer these proposals in this spirit. If some think them irreverent
of present academic institutions they are not irreverent of Popper's
proposals for what is the best foundation of science, as far as I can
tell.
In
short, then,
there is a flexibility which is not necessarily the
same as the indeterminism suggested by Niels Bohr. This indeterminism
may or may not hold. The flexibility component may also hold or not
hold but I do not suggest it is the same.
For
the
indeterminism suggested by Bohr involves a tight connection
with the Heisenberg uncertainty principle and the flexibility component
that I propose is not a vehicle of any such proposed principle.
Indeed,
I would
suggest that one must be very careful in proposing
anything such as a 'principle' in physics, because it sounds like
something irrefutable and beyond theory.
So
in the physics
foundation that I propose, there is but one such
principle, the principle of wholeness, and I will emphasize ways to put
it in a refutable form so it can be scientific and I will not, I think,
propose further principles -- not even the speed of light or
relativity. Rather, these other aspects I will refer to as theoretical
by-products or as 'tendencies', even if extremely stable tendencies.
In
particular, I
suggest that the central role of light can be given a
theoretical explanation in terms of the supermodels as follows:
Let
light not be
any particular kind of mass or particle in itself but
rather let it be the notion of a connection between anything and
anything else, most generally. In particular, let it be the connection
that may occur, as if nonlocally, between two neighbouring positions in
a spacetime grid. We will return to this idea to see how it can go
together with the notion of the photon quantum.
Going
back to what
I said about the importance of being careful not to
include the idea of all of time, as the quintessence of all (possible)
change, in an idea of the fourth dimension, but rather have a notion of
a somewhat flexible future which nevertheless has some component of
reality to it in alignment with what follows from Einstein's ideas, I
will suggest that, instead of spacetime or time-space, we say
space-duration.
The
space-duration
has a reality because if it has no reality then it
is hard to allow for such patterns as accounted elegantly for in
general relativity theory, in which the manifest moment of one process
may refer to something which is not the manifest moment of another
process, and vice versa. We need an expansion of space beyond the 3d
and it involves somehow something future-like and something past-like
but we agree with the sentiment of quantum theory that it may not be
THE future but rather A future. So this we can call space-duration.
In
the
space-duration, there should be, conceptually speaking, room for
probability densities.
What
then of the
concept of time? In a conversation with Holger
Bech-Nielsen at the Copenhagen Bohr Institute, he suggested to me that
time is the quintessence of all change. While he drew other
implications from this general proposal than I do, I will go along with
his suggestions and then say that we do not have a proper theory of
time and our musings about 4d is nowhere near of being an adequate
theory of time. Rather, the 4d of present physics is a theory of
certain sub-processes in time and these we can more modestly call
'duration'. This is my proposal. It would be too pretentious to speak
of 'time' in present physics just as it would be too pretentious to
speak of the existence of God based on current relativity theory or
quantum theory. (I am grateful to discussions with physicist Astri
Kleppe on related themes on a number of occasions.)
So,
I will qualify
what I said a little earlier, that space-time is a
supermodel: we can now say that space-duration is a supermodel.
Space-duration,
moreoever, is a supermodel that in part has its own
connections, grid-wise -- proposing here, also in alignment with
proposals in quantum physics, that space is grained rather than
continous - and also can have connections beyond itself, to other
supermodels.
The
connections
within the space-duration is by virtue of the typical
kind of structure and activity that can go on in any supermodel and not
by any arbitrary or artificial ad hoc hypothesis created for one
supermodel.
*
We
will now, in
this explorative unfoldment of the theory, take a break
in the questions of physics to focus on questions of a language of
physics. I do not think that the revised tools of Newton and Leibniz
into partial derivatives and differential integration are suitable for
providing a full overview over the implications of the findings in
experimental modern physics as of the twentieth century. I do think
that an entirely new kind of physics language is called for. In
bringing computers in, I do not see computers as merely a tool to play
out the consequences of that old mathematics, but rather as providing a
sense of a more dynamic and higher-level way of thinking about science.
In this light, I do appreciate some of the impulse of Wolfram, the man
behind Mathematica and who has produced some suggestions on what he
calls 'a new way of doing science' in a recent book that I looked at; I
do not, however, see in his work so far a qualified understanding of
the real implications of nonlocality nor any sense of the actual notion
of infinity as brought out in an earlier chapter here. So I do not
concur with the exact form that his work has taken, but, for the sake
of plurality, I think his independent style and impulse is lively and
worth the while. The impulse of Erwin Lazslo, while much more informed
on the nonlocality aspect, I also would call on in the name of
plurality, though I do not think his appreciation of the levels with
which nonlocality is organised for all phenomena (as I see it) is
adequately played out in his (perhaps over-focussed and not entirely
well-informed) distinction between the two types of waves he operates
with in his recent writings. Again, I recommend the dialogical
importance that people outside of celebrated physics communities doing
independent work; but it is important that we do not loose hold of the
refutability aspect, and Lazslo does not seem to emphasize the
refutability enough of his science concept as far as I can see.
As
for superstring
theory, M theory, and the like, I regard them as
important in some ways, and interesting in some ways, just as
Sheldrake's theory of morphogenetic resonance and Bohm's theory of the
implicate order; but as yet not a fully insightful production whch is a
theory of science proper. M theory has components of interest but it is
not adequately simple nor clear in its informal conception; and
therefore it does not matter (much) whether the formal achievement is
what it is -- namely that some formal bringing together of general
relativity theory elements and quantum theory elements happens
abstractly in it. It is not a theory as much as a complex and rather
intelligent excersise in equation-cracking without much reference to
reality nor to any coherent understanding of reality. Equation-cracking
is interesting but it is not the essence of insightful physics, of
course.
As
to the
manhattan language, the data is described through another
standard scheme called XML, which is nothing but a simple
generalisation of the syntax used in the worldwide internet, called
HTML. XML is literally 'eXtended htML' and involves the idea of a
rather free structure with segments beginning with
<name_of_segment> and finishing with </name_of_segment>.
The sense of freedom echoes the rather anarchistic or networking
impulse of how I would like physics to be represented (rather than as a
hierarchy).
The XML parser used here is written in Java 1.1.8 (like many other
things in the Green Cat which I have put together for you for this
book), utilizing open source GNU GPL code by Daeron
Meyer, also included in its original source form at the CDROMs as
according to its license; the XML
parsing with its graphical 3d visualisation is one part of the
manhattan language; the rest I have written myself. To be more precise,
the changes of the XML is in a new language specifically made for a
unified theory incorporating the essence of supermodel thinking, with
luck.
Each moment finds
its reflection in an XML-file. Each moment, or manifest present, as
seen from one observer, can be changed as for its perspective, scaled
etc, before one proceeds to the next moment (by the click of a button).
This is in order that the actual motions can be studied in slow detail;
there is no needless plastic-fantastic elaboration or glossifying here;
I have played before with many such 3d software solutions, but
eventually I came to respect most that which shows the actual dots or
lines or whatever with no further ado. For here lies the space to think
clearly, to find out the essence of what we are thinking; but if we
polish the corners and shine flashy lights and apply 'texture' image
mapping and all that, we are providing a temporary illusion which
prevents simulation clarity rather than enhancing it. That is why I
have found the very many available packages of the '3d animation' kind
uninteresting as far as a language for physics goes.
A single manhattan program (we can say
manhattan without a capital 'M' all the time as is the convention in
some programming languages like Larry Wall's perl) is thus a dyad, it
consists of two
texts, a text which is the data and a text which is the active program
part. The data part is whatever.xml and the active or interactive part
must have the same name but a different extension, namely .txt.
XML is merely data structure, not a
programming language.
Below
you will see
three .xml examples, and three .txt examples. The manhattan language
proper is mostly the .txt part but in a broader sense it includes this
particular .xml structure also. The xml structure is rather
self-documentary and easy to see through; that is why I have included
it.
When
you start up
the manhattan language, it automatically loads the
first physics illustration, which is called supermodel1. The file
supermodel1.xml together with the manhattan codes in a different
file with the same main name, supermodel1.txt, constitute the startup
pair of files when we start up the manhattan formalism simulator.
I believe that the programs or formal illustrations of the supermodel
theory are self-explanatory; especially so when you also do experiments
with the computer as well as with your own thought, perhaps also
changing the syntax, seeing what happens; making alternatives. You may
want to expand manhattan as language, and you will find that Green Cat
is easy to change in almost every important sense: for everything in it
can be recompiled almost by a click of a button or something like that.
It does presuppose that you know Java 1.1 from Sun Microsystems, which,
by some criterions, may be considered to be the first absolutely global
graphical standard language; it is entirely free, and open source
alternatives to Sun Microsystem's own compilers and the like exist in
plenty. I considered simply giving the models in the Java language but
I felt that all the dozens of languages I have made for myself
suggested something more concise, sharp, to the point, as a finale in
my career as far as computers go (for now I turn to painting and
informal talks and computers will only come in for occasional fun, I
think).
The
dyad of .xml
and .txt constitute each formalisation, as I said. What is the
relationship between a formalisation and a theory?
I regard it, along with Popper, essential for a theory to be
refutable. When we think of it, there is nothing about sheer formal
logic or equations
by themselves, in abstract space so to speak, which is refutable.
Refutability is a mental quality and concerns the
mental essence of a view of reality and in how we relate it to that
which is beyond itself. An equation is basically an
extreme simplification. No theory of physics or of any other science is
merely a rule or merely an axiom or merely a set of aximoms or set of
rules or equation; the theory proper is mental and these things can
come in to make certain elements of it more clear in some ways.
So, a formalisation can be considered an exemplification of
some features of a view. This means that we can regard, for instance,
Newton's equations as illustrations of some features of Newton's theory
of reality. The theory proper is not the formal. The equations by
themselves have no other reference than the entire context which may
wrap them up with informal clarity; this clarity would be part of the
theory.
Properly speaking, a theory is an item
of philosophy, a dance of thought, thought which is humble to the
greatness of reality or actuality, the ocean of nonthought or silence,
which says: reality is always more than any theory of it. Reality is
always more than this thought. It is always the 'more than', even more
than any thought, even more than this very thought of 'more than'. As
such, it is the infinite. A living and open infinity can be felt,
sensed, perceived in a view which is recreated in each mind by a
creative act.
The
three physics
programs are simple models of moving 3d which relate,
abstractly, to a big deal of the thoughts presented in the physics
chapters as to the likely structure of the universe as seen from the
material angle of present-day modern physics, slightly re-interpreted
to get general relativity and quantum physics on a common footing, and
strongly extended so as to get nonlocality going in biological
situations in terms of the third program formalism, which describes an
experiment of a refutable kind: if this experiment does not come out as
predict, 'the theory is dust and ashes', to quote Einstein. I am pretty
sure that it will come out as predicted but if it doesn't, I will add a
chapter to the effect! However, I leave that to people who love doing
experimental physics; this is largely an intuitive initiative and
somehow I know by heart it is coherent with a sense of the universe as
intuitively experienced through the dance of synchronicities.
In supermodel theory, nonlocality plays a deep and strong role, much
more so than in conventional quantum theory. It is at the heart of the
theory, in that everything is seen as if 'woven' of nonlocality and
locality is rather what needs to be 'explained'. When anything
interacts with anything, nonlocality is involved. Every form of
interaction involves a relationship to the frequency of the energy in
some way; when some energy is supposed to 'read' another energy, this
involves that there are changes involved so that precision is limited,
as far as these energy types are concerned anyway (and we do not
postulate other energy types here though in principle an infinity of
other energy types are possible and imaginable and to my mind even
likely).
The Heisenberg uncertainty postulates are of a nature which intrigues
me, in a way which may proceed to suggest new forms of physics
theorizing altogether. I wish to add to this description of supermodel
theory that entirely new forms of supermodels may be contained within
the vestiges of present supermodel theory as it interacts with these
postulates, in a sense which I feel would come as a surprise (a
pleasant surprise).
It may be argued that flexibility is, in isolation, not a refutable
concept. But it is unrealistic to require of every portion of a theory
that it is refutable in a trivial sense. I feel that the notion of
flexibility, when applied in a careful way to any theory of the
universe, assert a humility in thought which is fully and deeply
compatible with the popperian approach of refutability.
What I will next
suggest
has occurred to me regularly and I am sure neither Bohr nor Einstein
nor anyone else of the prominent physicsts at the time would easily
agree to what I say in this paragraph -- and yet I feel it is called
for: many of the
deep divisions and fragmentations of theoretical nature in physics
arose in the late 1920s and in the 1930s and they were not solved in
the 1940s when Einstein and Bohr etc were still alive. My postulate is
that not only did the political tensions, and the tendencies towards
getting into the atrocities of World War II, tend to distract these
noble minds from being at their fullest potential, but it may also be
that the fear of uncovering an even bigger bomb, by several orders of
magnitude, than the (at that time, only imagined) atomic bomb, could
have diminished their interest in actually developing physics further
-- at least at a preconscious level.
Let
us then not
emphasize the technical or technological features of
the supermodel theory, but rather consider it a work of art, and with
the quality of refutability that can give it a flavour of science. I
call on responsibility of an infinite degree in every individual
focussing on theories in physics, so that we minimize the plausibility
that new bombs of any kinds can be constructed as a result of our
pursuit of insights into reality. For the more we touch truth, the less
we must bring the virus of natural exploitation or egohood into our
work. If physics is gasoline, let us not ignite it. However, it would
be fun to find a way to create leisure spacecrafts which have warp
speeds and which are environmentally friendly, and life-supportive for
humans. This is a peaceful vision of the kind of technology that may
come from a good supermodel theory.
In
the supermodel
theory, there is one and but one principle, that of
the movement towards wholeness (PMW). By 'principle' I do not mean that
it should be considered as in any way 'above' the notion of the
refutability of all our scientific theory. I merely mean that in this
theory, it is the by far most essential point; but if the theory is
tested honestly and strongly and nothing of what it predicts comes out
as predicted, experimentally, then of course the principle along with
everything else in the theory will be washed away (and if so, and only
if so, I will garantee a new edition of this book, in which the
refutation is published, and perhaps I will work out a completely new
theory).
What
then of the
socalled Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle? Since we
indeed are encapsulating, in our theory, a picture of reality -- or a
model which claims to have something to do with reality in ways which
involves refutability, to be precise -- we must take a stand as to the
Heisenberg and Bohr notion of complementarity between observables such
as position and momentum.
It
will be noticed
that GRT proceeds without postulating any
uncertainty or indeterminacy in position.
In
trying to
ascertain whether the complementary or mutual
indeterminacy is merely epistemological or if it is also ontological
(ie, having to do with reality, not just the experience of reality),
physicists have explored whether some kind of fluctuation may be said
to underlie phenomena, say, at the rims of what they imagine to be
singularities in space-duration ('black holes with hairs', as Hawking
quipped).
It
seems that
whenever physicists look consistently for such
fluctuations, they tend to find them.
Can
we then take
it that the complementarity of position and momentum
is nothing but a masking of fluctuating actually precise positions and
precise momenta, a masking which physicists do not know any means of
penetrating -- or is it to be taken in a more ontological sense? You
follow?
Bohm
postulated
that an electron is a particle at all times and that
the complementarity comes in when we try to ascertain what this
position is. Bohr would have nothing of it, and postulated that there
is some other state of affairs, and that position somehow comes into
being as it is called for, such as in an experimental situations
looking for position.
Logically,
even
though Bohr's position may be right, Bohm's cannot be
excluded as untenable -- if then the position wildly fluctuates in a
way which is not just local (as J S Bell has worked out with great
precision in his clarification of the socalled proof by J S Neumann
that hidden variable variations of quantum theory are not possible).
However,
if Bohm's
version is correct, or some other approach which
gives a reality to position at all times, like the many
worlds-interpretation, or like a modified nonlocal pilot wave version
as of de Broglie, then it is not at all impossible that Bohr's position
can be refuted and that, by some new technological means weaved of
stuff not adhering too strictly to the limitations flowing from
Planck's constant could look behind the mask of the complementarity and
bring up more information that Heisenberg's uncertainty principle would
allow. It is important to be open to these possibilities and not
emotionally reject anyone on the basis of a tradition.
A
computer game
may illustrate the point. Imagine that we play a game
called XYZ1 and each time we play XYZ1 a red ball is at a different and
also hidden position in the game. It may be in this or that box, say,
and on clicking on a box the box opens to reveal the red ball. So let's
say that there are eight boxes, and some of them may contain blue balls
and only one of them, if any, contains a red ball; or perhaps two red
balls.
In
playing the
game, the person clicks on the box that she guesses
might contain the ball.
Now,
we might
program this game in two ways. Either we can, at startup,
call on some kind of RFFG (relatively free fluctuation generator) so as
to actually position a ball or two (or none) in this or that box.
Or
we can program
it so that only when the person is clicking on boxes,
we call on an RFFG so as to position, with some probability, a red ball
there.
The
former is a
metaphor over Bohm's suggestion and the latter is a
metaphor over Bohr's suggestion.
So
these are two
games, the M-game and the R-game, let's say.
Is
the M-game or
the R-game most representative of the actual case of
the electron?
Many
physicists,
leaning towards a formalistic positivistic streak in
physics, might suggest that it doesn't matter, it is philosophy not
physics to ask that question, as long as our mathematical numerical
predictions hold true in laboratories -- who cares what is where when
we don't look?
However,
there are
subtle differences regarding refutability, the
quality so foundational to physics it is more strong than any
tradition, more strong than any academic institution or academic
authority as a person, and so it is not just some vague kind of
philosophy but a question of science to ask it.
If
we say: who
cares? Then we are taking a stand which is rather
irrefutable. That is not scientific.
We
should care,
because in caring for the actual situation, we come
with alternatives which lead to different kinds of experiments when we
unfold and unravel the implications duitfully in the coming decades,
giving duration and consciousness to our work.
For
instance, one
may postulate that there is actually no such thing as
a given electron with a given position before it is measured, there is
something else, some vague open kind of potential perhaps, and then
this potential can lead to a series of postulates.
Or
we can
postulate that there are definite positions all along. Or
something else, like the many world-interpretations or middle-things
between these. Whatever we decide on, we should make it explicit but
not only explicit but as testable as we can. Because science is
sticking your head out.
I
have been
wondering about the reality behind the quantum positions
since people first told me about it. I am still wondering. However, we
are implementation a concrete theory and so I will make a concrete
proposition about this, perchance by my 'intellectual intuition' of
what is most elegant and what feels most coherent with innumerable
aspects of reality as I have sensed them. Here it is:
If
de Broglie or
Bohm were right, then any spread of possible positions
for something like an electron is a feature of an electron in addition
to a position for an electron, and this spectrum of possible or likely
positions is in nonlocal connection with the electron and affecting its
movement.
In
our theory, it
would mean that the supermodel representing a
spectrum of upcoming likely positions for an electron co-exists with a
connection of the electron with one unambigious position in each moment
of the space-duration at all times.
If,
in our
supermodel theory, we were to take the R-game approach
rather than the M-game approach, we would sometimes suspend the
connection of an electron with a particular unambigious region of a
moment in space-duration.
Let
me, before I
suggest my own intuition, suggest that while I am not
against the thought that there may be many worlds in our universe (or
"many universes in parallel"), and that I am not against the thought
of many open futures, I feel that there is a greater likelihood that
something like a principle of movement towards wholeness (PMW) goes on
than a mechanical fragmentation of the universe into a zillion
universes, one for each possibility, in each instant. For the latter is
mechanical and the PMW suggests a more organic sense of the universe,
and my personal intuition is that there is an organic wholeness to the
synchronistic order of things. So the many-worlds interpretation appear
to me to be a step back to mechanical reductionism as far as the
unfoldment of processes go (even though it is wildly expansionist as
concerns the amount of worlds).
Let
me also point
out that Louis de Broglie's idea of a pilot wave is
somewhat closer to the mathematics (indeed, the simple mathematics) of
early Schroedinger version of quantum phenomena, but that Bohm's notion
of the quantum potential involves a somewhat more intricate mathematics.
However,
the
original pilot wave theory did not treat measurement
situations as subtly as Bohm treated them; and so it did not come out
correctly, numerically. It is a feature of Bohm's theory that
measurements are considered 'mututal transformations' between some
quantum systems and other quantum systems rather than an interaction
between a quantum system and a classical mechanical system (as in
Bohr's approach). If you take Bohm's idea of measurement to de
Broglie's approch, it seems that it is a valid working possibility
(thanks to George Simpson for comments on this; I have also read some
of de Broglie's writings, once, late in his long life and then he
described how he had left the Copenhagen Interpretation and dropped the
approach of Niels Bohr again, and thus revised the theory he had as
young and that he trusted it to be clearer and possibly more close to
the truth that Bohr's approach.)
I
fully support
Louis de Broglie's theory updated on the measurement
situation. That is my intuition.
Let
me qualify,
however, how far I would push de Broglie's pilot wave
theory as far as the physics of the future goes:
If
we have a
picture of an electron in one position, and then, guided
by the pilot wave, in a sudden different position then we have a
discreteness and, by a finer duration resolution, could there not be an
intermediate state in which an electron has neither positions? I would
say, certainly, yes -- there is a whole range of theoretical
possibilities that I sense one day can be absolutely critical for such
things as stellar travel. However I will not venture in the present
manuscript to do more than saying -- and then there may be a lot more!
-- as to this issue. But let me grant this insight to Bohr that there
may be a real role of the suspension of common observables; however it
may have been somewhat misplaced to say that it concerns everything
that happens in between measurements.
So
I have given a
somewhat qualified support to the M-game. Let me,
however, point out that David Bohm himself was a creative genius with
many positions in parallell, and while he at a talk at the Bohr
institute in the 1990s said, according to newspapers, "The electron IS
a particle", he did also imagine that both quantum and relativity
phenomena are but expressions of a deeper implicate, finely woven flux
which is beyond all concepts of particles. So also Bohm would say,
sure, it might be that there is something like a cosmic moment in which
an electron does not have a fixed position. This I can say also
because, although I had read a great deal of Bohm's writings, I tended
to ask him such questions as goes 'in between' the typical views of
what Bohm's opinions were, and in doing so, I never once missed the
point -- he always accepted such suggestions. He was a possibilist in
the true sense of the word.
Let
me now deduce
the implications of this proposal. This proposal
implies that the measurement situations, however much they lead to a
sense of complementary indeterminacy or uncertainty, does not exactly
show the reality of the case. Nor is it completely out of the question
that this complementarity, at that level, can be circumvented if some
special subtle matter could address things without getting so entangled
into the matter it is measuring.
In
doing away with
the complementarity principle as applied to position
and momentum, let me again give some credence to complementarity as a
concept applied to physics -- for again I feel Bohr struck an important
note in bringing it in. Indeed he seems to have got the idea while
doing free walking in the mountains in Norway, while Heisenberg, young
and restless at his Bohr institute, came up with the uncertainty
principle equations; they met and sort of combined the two (this I have
from some memoirs written by Heisenberg; however, it should be noted
that Heisenberg and Bohr were not at all at the same friendly terms
after World War II.)
For
I fully
support the feeling that complementarity, in many senses,
pervade all Nature. I see, in a way, the natural numbers beginning with
2 or two, more than 1 or one, because if you want to teach the concept
of counting to a child, it really begins by showing the similarity
between any pair of things and any other pair of things.
Likewise,
we see a
lot of mirroring, such as of positive and negative
'charges', as they are called: and this is again a complementarity.
There
is also the
feeling that life involves such complementarities as
the masculine or reaching out and the feminine or attracting inwards.
Then
again, we
find the complementarity involved in proposing something
and then seeking a refutation of it.
We
have also the
dialogue concept with the absolutely significant
complementarity of I-Thou as proposed, poetically and as a stroke of
genius, by Martin Buber. I am grateful to tons of dicussions with my
father Stein Braten on all issues of complementarity and also creative
use of computer programming in relation to philosophy -- since early
childhood!
So
in all ways I
can say, at a general level, by all means adopt the
concept of complementarity and seek to find it, instead of erecting
monopolistic, monolithic (or even fascistic) structures.
Complementarity is about life.
In
bringing
complementarity into physics at a philosophical level, I
think that Bohr has done the world a great service, as he also did in
being the first who edged out a workable sketch of the atom.
The
complementarity concept is in a complementary relation to the
continuity concept. Bohr and Einstein thus had a complementarity
philosophical perspective.
Let
us now say
that we can re-apply a generic complementarity to the
electron: not anymore as much to position and momentum (except in
ordinary measurements), but with regard to its localised energy and its
spectrum of possible positions in the upcoming future, as represented
by a supermodel.
For
further
discussion on possibilities and issues at a philosophical
and also mathematical level I refer to David Bohm and Basil Hiley, "The
Undivided Universe, an ontological interpretation of quantum theory",
the last book Bohm ever worked on.
What
of light? How
come that light exhibits particle-like properities
sometimes?
I
find the
situation of the socalled 'phonon' rich with suggestive
evidence of what may go on in the case of the 'photon'.
In
the 'phonon'
situation, we create a wave of a sound-like character
in a medium like a crystal, and we do so in a context where the whole
situation is measured on an extremely fine basis, in which de Broglie's
relation of energy being related to the frequency times Planck's
constant is related to so that we get an energy of the sound waves
which is close to the individual quanta. For quantum mechanics is a
theory of all energy, to start with, anyway.
We
create sound
waves, waves that are waves, waves which have a
definite and known medium in the sense that anything can be a known
medium for a wave. So the situation is clear-cut: there is a wave.
There is a wave and there is no reason to assume that this wave is
carried out by means of some mysterious particles of sound which have
temporary positions or no positions or a spectrum of positions and yet
-- interestingly -- if we measure the arriving energy with a focus on
position, then Voila!, we get particle-like eruptions of energies with
adherence to the idea that no quantum of energy should be divided, just
as for light, for electrons etc.
For
it is a
postulate in QMT that energy arrives, if at all, as whole
packets of energy no less than that given by de Broglie's relation.
If
we had known
this when we had formulated the measurement ways of
energies we might have defined a kind of energy size so that Planck's
constant in effect would have been one. For quantum theory suggests
that there is a basic, indivisible 'coin' of energy.
When
we meet
continous phenomena such as of light at a human scale then
a physicist might suggest that this is an appearance, and that if we
look a lot more closely, aided by adequate technology, we will see that
it is not continous but grained, and de Broglie's relation gives us the
size of the grainage.
The
amazing thing
is that the PWs, or the pilot waves, which in our theory are
supermodels of a special kind operating on any other supermodels, seem
to organize the sound energy so that it arrives in packets even though
it is definitely a wave phenomenon, in all its appearances.
A
pilot wave (PW)
supermodel can then organize any kind of energy not
just particle energy and when it is brought into a situation where
position is measured the PW supermodels create something of the effect
of a particle.
This
is roughly
how I suggest we explain photons (although their media
is more complex, involving a two-dimensionality in each node, among
other things).
What
the
supermodel theory then contains is a postulate that light is a
wave-like energy which is guided by PW supermodels just like any other
kind of energy. It is however not just any kind of energy but an energy
arising by a certain kind of connectedness involving the magnetic and
the electric aspects of the supergrid or supermodel called
SPACE_DURATION.
The
electric and
the magnetic aspect is in a way yet another example of
complementarity, which is found so often in nature. The magnetic rather
folds on itself and the electric rather spreads out and they have
relations akin to a two-dimensionality, a two-dimensionality also found
in the PW supermodels; they are consistently wrought up with the
complex number factor i when put in the Schroedinger equations.
(Indeed, the Schroedinger equation is very near to the wave equation
for classical guitar strings and the like, but with an additional
component which comes from adding i and h, or the complex number
dimension and Planck's constant).
Let
us also note
that the mysterious 'shells of the electron' in the
bohrian view of the atom prior to quantum mechanics got with de Broglie
a beautiful explanation which led to a lot of good physics, and still
does: namely that the pilot waves form a sort of standing waves around
the atomic core and the rules of standing waves being what they are --
that they need to be a whole number of half-wavelengths or else the
standing waves interfere destructively with one another -- leads to the
quantum 'jumps' between possible energy states of the electron around
the core. Add to this the two-dimensionality of the PW supermodels and
the standing waves are of course a lot more complex than mere guitar
string waves but it is fundamentally much of the same picture; and it
is indeed a picture.
Let
me point out
that Bohr suggested that the imaginary number i
involves, when it is used in physics, a phenomenon which should not be
considered really existing but merely a mathematical abstraction. I
think that this statement, if made precise in a rather obvious way, is
wrong.
If
this statement
is made precise in this way -- that an equation which
involves the imaginary number i cannot possibly depict anything really
existing -- then we see that it is unlikely to be correct, because the
imaginary number i is merely a vehicle for bringing an additional
dimension to the numbers we invoke, so that they can rotate and not
just fluctuated up and down. So, for instance, we could bring in the
imaginary number i so as to account for all the different
clock-movements on the clocks of people's arm while in no way implying
that these clocks are merely mathematical abstractions not really
existing out there. The imaginary number i is no more imaginary than
any other element of mathematics, for all of mathematics is imaginary
anyway.
I
feel it is
unfair to critisize any physicist too much but we should
know that the influence on physics in the twentieth century by Niels
Bohr is tremendous and vast, it involves a similar influence that Freud
exerted on the science of mind -- and so we sometimes should lift into
attention elements of what such an influence said in order to destill
it or negate portions of it when it is important. Or else it can reside
there, in our preconsciousness, as something which create unnecessary
friction.
So
let us not be
misled by the phrase 'complex number' either. It is
not all that complex, in fact it is one of the simpler and more
beautiful structures in mathematics. However if I were to make that bit
of mathematics all over again I would have called it something like
'rotation numbers'.
When
we say
'rotation number' we at once see why the number pi
(3.14...etc) comes up again and again in the quantum equations also
involving 'i' and 'h' (Planck's constant).
So
just as
space-duration has a two-dimensional complementary feature
in the electric and the magnetic so can any PW supermodel have the two
dimensions involving the pilot wave, or rotational, numbers.
Then
I wish to
address the question of whether all energies are
fundamentally of just one (complementary) type, and to this I sense a
simplicity which is also in full coherence with Einsteins work on the
'equality' of mass and energy (through the factor of the square of c),
and I say, intuitively, yes.
If,
then, as it
appears, that the simplest and purest kind of energy
there is, is the weaving of electric and magnetic waves together as
Maxwell beautifully described -- however in some sense which must be
supplied with quantum insights, ie, the PW supermodels (in our case) --
then to some extent we seem to be suggesting that everything is 'woven
of light'.
In
the quest for
simplicity and also for having a coherent picture of
reality in this supermodel theory, let me proceed further along this
line. I will now state some more intuitions which can be each
considered eclectically but which also works together as a symphony in
the present modelling of reality.
Many
physicists
have asked: if the pilot waves, or probability wave
function, have a reality then why is it not measured directly?
At
the same time,
they have acknowledged that the gravitation waves, or
waves of curvature, are in general so weak compared to what is called
'the other forces' that they can hardly be measured at all with their
equipment.
I
propose that the
PW supermodels manifest themselves through extremely
weak gravitation waves, picked up by each relevant component, such as
an electron, by means of an extraordinarily subtle form of resonance.
In
alignment with
what Bohm has proposed, I suggest that when an
electron is seen to move in accordance with something like a pilot
wave, it moves on its own accord rather like a ship moving on its own
accord on the basis of what it has picked up on the radar.
Also
in alignment
with what Bohm has proposed, and for which there
exists, I have heard, some vague empirical justifications, I suggest
that the electron has structure.
This
structure,
moreover, is highly complex. If it is 'woven of light',
as in the present suggestion, and the discreteness of space-duration is
directly involved in the structure of light, then there is plenty of
scale distance between light as such and the electron.
My
intuition urges
me to say more, however. My feeling is that we can
make a picture of an electron in which it itself creates, as it were,
its own curvature to propell it in a certain direction.
The
same can be
said for protons, neutrons etc. That they pick up
extremely weak waves of curvature so as to lead them to project a
curvature. When different waves of curvature intersect so as to be in
resonance with the particles this may result in the flexibility
feature, which we spoke of in an earlier chapter as distinguishing
supermodels from any kind of programmatic text. (Let us keep this in
mind while we make a concrete computer model; supermodels are more
advanced structures than program texts.)
A
question is,
what is it that makes an electron into an electron --
ie, how can we explain its particular mass, charge etc? And the same
for neutrons etc.
My
proposal is
that all these particles has surfaced by means of what
Rupert Sheldrake once called 'habits of cosmos'; or, as we may say,
there are similarities and contrasts involved, perpetuating themselves
by means of the PMW (the principle of movement towards wholeness). They
may have come about themselves by means of some flexibility or some
fluctuation; we cannot rule out, however, that there are subtle origins
for this (as well, or as an alternative, in combination with some
relative degree of fluctuation -- or indeed, by some other principle,
like similarity with an already existing whole of the universe, etc
etc).
In
any case, since
light involves the magnetic and the electric, it
involves the sensitivity to PW supermodels, it involves the
relationship within the space-duration of curvature etc, and it is also
microscopic enough, as compared to neutrons, protons etc, to be a
possible vehicle for the structuring of all these 'known' material
components, then it can make sense to say that light weaves it all.
I propose, for the sake of simplicity, that there is but one medium,
for both curvature in GRT, electromagnetism in QMT, and wave functions
understood as pilot waves, and this medium is such that at each node in
this flexible four-dimensional matrix, there is a two-dimensionality of
curvature, a two-dimensionality of frequency, and a directedness (as
momentum, very roughly) of any such energy as indicated by the
frequency. The two-dimensionality of frequency is the electric and the
magnetic, the two-dimensionality of curvature reflects any neighbouring
energy (as well as this) with large-sized numbers; tiny numbers
(relatively) speaking reflects information from pilot waves as to
changes of direction. The directedness will feed the pilot waves and
they will feed back. The pilot waves are created by the PMW, the
principle of a tendency of movement towards wholeness, operating not
just on 3d but flexibly over 4d (yoga4d..;). Each pilot wave is a
supermodel, having behaviour and flexibility, representing an
enhancement of contrast and or similarities as to other supermodels
with which it interconnects. SPACE_DURATION is a huge and particularly
stable and well-structured supermodel; they all have the
two-dimensionality in each node and potentially can act to transfer
energy. In an extended version, they can do the warp-like tunnelling of
one portion of SPACE_DURATION to somewhere else.
In this supermodel theory, we find that this 'atoms' of actuality, the
supermodels, are mind-like structures relating to themselves and each
other in a conversational like, making up a many-dimensional universe
which gradually unfolds, with an open future. The pilot waves are
supermodels fostered, sustained and dissolved according to PMW. This is
the most succinct summing up of the theory, which is however in nature
informal. It is expressed as to only some of its many features in the
formal language which is based closely on Forth by Charles Moore in
interaction with the XML/3d as in my version of it; see references for
the compiler in the Green Cat /home/winner directory, where full open
sources are kept. I regard the theory as consciously vague and open as
to the depths of uncertainty relations. I do not mean to say that all
features of uncertainty nor of curvature are illustrated in the
computer languages. The empirical novel predictions of the applications
of PMW to EPR-like situations must pertain to a more complex situation
than the one illustrated. The empirical refutable predictions are not
here presented in a numerical format, but in the format of a clear idea
which can be translated by active physicists to exact numbers.
For clarity, I will state the third EPR-like situation, which is
indicated in but a few features in the formal model below: here, we
start with an initial condition without local contact with a number of
particles, not just two, and instead of local entrainment we build up a
unique pattern of activation in this set of particles, say ten or ten
thousand, by some kind of entrainment chamber inserting a fingerprint
frequency or something of that nature which has a near-perfect set of
similarities and contrasts involved, in a number of macroscopically
spatially separate laboratories with atomically exact clocks. We want
to set up a nonlocality without local contact; we want to check that it
is not succumbing to speed of light limitations; we want to create it
through a postulated PMW which might presumbly touch all the universe,
and so we must try and try again looking for a rather unique pattern
(perhaps DNA). With the rather unique pattern, we will after a while
let mostly all particles involved be exposed to a gentle change, akin
to the measurement situation in the EPR-like situation. This change
will be instantly followed up ('instantly' in the Aspect sense, at
least much faster than the speed of light) by a measurement on the
not-changed particles. We are looking for a pattern of correlation of
similar contrasts and contrasting similarities on the particles that we
did not change ourselves. If we find it, it is in tune with what I
regard as a trivial yet biologically and spiritually interesting
implication of supermodel theory. If we don't find it, supermodel
theory belongs to the museum of misguided proposals.
So, the third EPR-like situation as described in a Forth-like language
which modifies the XML/3d-model is a lot more complex than in that
two-particle version, but we can sense the simplicity of the PMW since
it in fact was used in how supermodel theory accounts for the more
classical EPR-like situation (with local contact first, see
supermodel1.txt and supermodel1.xml).
Supermodel theory incorporates curvature essentially, not just through
an artificial type of 'graviton'-related forces; this is shown in
supermodel2.txt and supermodel2.xml, in which the EPR-like situation
unfolds in the presence of some very strong curvature like a
singularity in SPACE_DURATION (a socalled 'black hole'). We see that
this comes in as effortlessly as it could come, and that shows that we
have a rather coherent proposal in supermodel theory, in which we can
let go of certain dogmas pertaining to the original forms of GRT and
QMT and focus on the positive empirical content as reflected in a fresh
new perceptive way in which the priority is to the mind-like
correlation fields or supermodels, which we can subtly and sensitively
feel to be at the ground for synchronicities. For these do not merely
concern elementary particles, but also, due to the the similarity and
contrast enhancement also constellations of such; however their pilot
wave communication requires extraordinary microscopic sensitivity which
is amplified and this amplication is perhaps more than metaphorical
what meditation is about.
We
also have, as
Richard Feynman, for instance, describes in his QED --
Quantum Electrodynamics -- a whole range of simple, interesting ways of
explaining things by means of the notion of the easy, spontaneous,
interconvertibility between light and matter particles; add to this
also the sense in which things can flow both ways in a space-duration
(which is no contradiction, in contrast to the conventional situation
of speaking of 'both ways in time').
While
Feynman may
have considered some parts of physics 'mere
mathematical abstraction' we do not need to go as far as he did at all
points.
What
about the
postulate of 'conservation of energy'? How can it hold
if indeed the electron and other particles sort of make their own walks?
However
it must be
clear that the notion of 'conservation of energy'
is, as also Bohm has pointed out, a statistical concept which does not
hold, necessarily, for individual quantum measurements. Indeed, on
giving energy to an electron emitter of the size of an electron we may
or may not get an electron, or maybe even more than one, as coming out
and being measured. So there is a tendency rather than a law that
energy is conserved at this level.
I
feel that the
word 'energy' is woven up with a lot of prejudices in
physics and that another concept might make the essential situation a
lot clearer.
For
if we rather
equate mass with energy and speak of a new measurement
standard of energy so that Planck's constant is effectively equal to
one, then what we might seem to have is position and tendencies for
position as curvature, as well as supermodels influencing these
curvatures.
It
is not
necessary to speak either of mass or energy because we can
speak of curvature; and the curvature is indeed a tendency for a
direction, a tendency, rather, for a new position.
In
this picture,
the complementarity which before was called 'position
- momentum' can rather be called 'position - tendency'.
We
see that we are
achieving, slowly, by assembling the fragmented
pieces of a great deal of high-level physics work for more than a
century, a greater and greater frame of simplicity and also wholeness
-- not a reductive simplicity, but a simplicity that can dance with the
actual complexity there is.
If
we would like
to focus on tendencies for position, ie, range of
positions, we can get something like a wave of this range, a wave which
admits of a frequency; in contrast, if we wish to focus on position, we
need to add waves (as Nick Herbert elegantly describes in his book
"Quantum Reality") so as to create a 'peak' at a single position. In
that way, the PW supermodel for position has a natural complementary to
that of tendency. I admit it is somewhat unclear or vague as formulated
on this stage, but as we evolve the formal model slowly, not being
eager for definitions before we have created a foundation in shared
insight into the matter stuff, we will probably get to the light,
together.
Rather
in
spinozistic (or pantheistic) terms, we can see each structure
such as an electron, proton or neutron, or whatever, as independently
'moving about', out of its own inner order; this inner order involves
in part a sensitivity which all light already has, by virtue of it
being a curvature with a PW supermodel, and in part a capacity for some
other of its light to 'shoot out' and create a curvature which pulls
the present correlation in a particular direction, as guided by the PW
supermodels to which it is in resonance.
Let
us speak of
this again: is a curvature moving a curvature? Let us
go to the einsteinian picture again, where it is spoken consistently of
correlations in a space-duration. So there is really not so much
pulling and pushing as mere curvature which indicates a world-line and
moments being manifests somehow flows through this world-line creating
the appearance of a particle in movement.
This
world-line
further appears to be fluctuating if we pursue the
pilot wave idea; for instance, in a double slit experiment the pilot
wave idea is that the particle, in the case where it is indeed a
particle like an electron involved, goes indeed through one not both
slits however the pilot wave refers nonlocally to both slits in its
guidance of the motion of the particle.
Empirically,
some
waves seems to spread out circularly or in all
available directions, whereas other waves seems to project like rays.
If light is a wave of the latter kind, however guided by PW
supermodels, it will then move as a ray to some extent, then possibly
shift direction, etc -- and the Feynmann mathematics gives indications
that this way of thinking can be numerically consistent with the
quantum theory predictions.
Yet
how can a
curvature project a curvature, as suggested just above?
Let us call into mind that if light is a 'basic' curvature, involving
also a basic nonlocal type of connection between one discrete point in
the space-duration and another, then this is extremely small compared
to something like an electron, and the curvature of the electron
involves a lot, lot more. In 'constructing' an electron with its
summarized big curvature out of the many many tiny curvatures, each
having capacities such as the electric and the magnetic, capacities
such as polarisation and the typical light-type of resonance, we can
indeed have the erection of a full-blown structure which in, effect,
can do a lot -- including use something of its own curvature to create
another curvature and then take it, or a lot of it, back again.
Again,
I wish to emphasize: a theory is per definition informal. A formal
theory is an absurd, self-contradictory thought. The formal cannot be
but an illustration.
We
will have three
examples, the EPR-like situation, illustrated in
manhattan as a program, the EPR-like situation effortlessly expanded
with curvature, to show that the formalism and also the theory are
willing to incorporate this type of general relativity theory structure
on an equal footing with quantum theory structures, and as a third
illustration, we will engage refutability by changing the EPR-like
situation in alignment with the approach of the theory as perception
and we will give a new testable experiment in a very general form, that
those who engage in quantum experiments can refine into a number of
concrete experiments with (hopefully) today's technology. If the
predictions do not meet the actual results, please scrap the theory of
supermodels. That is the reality of refutability.
To
retrace some of our steps, a theory is a
subtle, tacit and in some sense nonfinite mental
structure with, in good cases, plenty of areas of reference to the
world in a refutable sense. As such a theory cannot be 'formalized' but
selected components of it can be, I prefer to say, illustrated formally.
This
can be said
of theories in any domain as well as of this theory of
essential processes in the manifest universe. By 'essential processes'
I mean that the focus is not on concrete or specific processes, such as
stones or plants. By 'manifest' I mean, that which is more or less at
hand, excluding not the (likely) possibility that there is infinitely
more to be said about more subtle and less manifest levels, and even
infinitely many more aspects of this manifest level. I see no a priori
reason why there may not be many more forms of forces, energies and
matter, or other types of processes, in the manifest universe as we
know it.
What
I have done
is to generalize over the physics of the twentieth
century so as to address issues left rather unsolved by Einstein, de
Broglie, Bohm and Bohr, etc, in a way which makes sense in relation to
a world full of macroscopic nonlocality or synchronicity, which is
indeed the world as I directly experience it every day. The modified
version of the EPR with different initial conditions illustrate the
perceptive mechanism of the universe (the word 'mechanism' is meant in
a rather metaphorical and open manner, referring more precisely to
something infinite and beyond determination, in this case) which is so
that nonlocalities can be expected to be rather everywhere, not just
somewhere; and given suitable sensitive conditions, they can be picked
up also at a biological level.
By
'universe' (in
the above formulation) I mean to indicate a sense of
wholeness (rather as in Bohm's phrase 'the undivided universe' in the
title of his last book, with Hiley). I do not mean to exclude the
possibility of many parallel worlds and so on but to emphasize the
wholeness of 'what is', ie, existence as we know it, more or less.
The
theory of
supermodels as I propose it is not reductive for it does
not say, 'there is nothing but this', but rather it says: this is at
least what is.
In
the first
illustration of a formal nature I assume, with
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen, that some kind of meeting between two
particles have occured, following a gentle separation of twe particles
in a way which leaves an 'indistinguishiability of the wave function'
intact; after which some kind of measurement or other is performed on
one and maybe also the other particle.
The
entire
discussion around EPR is a great deal more complex and
subtle and involves a challenge by Bohr even to the very act of
describing the unmeasured 'system' as being composed of 'two
particles'. However, I do not attempt here to illustrate the classical
EPR but an EPR-like situation. Moreover, the EPR-like situation is
understood according to the supermodel theory not the Copenhagen
Interpretation. Because of the (neo)realist orientation of supermodel
theory we can visualize position of particles in each step, and
consider measurement rather as a particular nonlocal interaction
between particles and a set of particles constituting apparatus.
We
abstract out a
few elements of this situation. Due to the
flexibility of the supermodels, we will see fluctuations or dances,
derived from, in our formal illustration, the RF function.
Due
to the
existence of a common 'wave function' or Pilot Wave (PW) as
we like to say in supermodel theory, a portion of the fluctuations for
particle A will relate perhaps symmetrically to a portion of those of
particle B.
To
see the PW in
action, we should introduce a change for one of the
particles which can be metaphorical of the change which a measurement
introduces. Since, in supermodel theory, we are at liberty to model
each moment of unfoldment visually, we do not need to actually do much
out of the modelling of measurement apparatus. We must, however, not
commit the error of early de Broglie of regarding a measurement as an
event not in itself requiring pilot waves (ie, a 'classical physics' or
'mechanical' measurement situation must not be assumed). Otherwise, the
arguments of von Neuman would apply.
So
any measurement
action is wrought with uncertainties given by HUR,
the Heisenberg Uncertainty Relation (at least insofar as we are dealing
with Planck-governed matter and energy; and in twentieth century main
physics there is no empirical indiction of any other type of matter and
energy; however it is theoretically of course infinitely many ways in
which HUR might empirically be upset in the future and so such a
qualification -- specifying which types of matter and energy for which
HUR applies -- may one day be essential to physicists...).
Only
by keeping
this mind will the complexity of Bell's inequality be
seen to be necessary, as seen from the viewpoint of an experimentative
situation with the type of physical equipment which today's physicists
have at their disposal and which Aspect used.
Keeping
this
complexity of measurement in mind, we can nevertheless
simplify what we here formally illustrate, once we, as modellers
through the supermodel theory, have extra information of variables
which to the poor experimenting physicist is hidden. If these hidden
variables were local, or without a nonlocal PW, then von Neuman's
argument would apply. So to stay tuned to the actual theoretical
numerical predictions of both Copenhagen Interpretations and bohmian
interpretation of quantum theory, as regards EPR, we will be interested
in seeing how a mesaurement-like 'change' in relation to, say, particle
A, create only a portionally symmetric behaviour in particle B at the
same time. (Let me add here that 'at the same time' is a meaningful
phrase in supermodel theory because the whole unfoldment of the
four-dimensional SPACE_DURATION does have simultaniety, in contrast to
the limitations proposed in general relativity theory; and see the
discussions above for how we achieved this -- by a laxing on the notion
of time with regard to the fourth dimension, saying instead it involves
'duration', in short. Nevertheless, it is speculation to say that it is
exactly 'the same time'; there is of course infinitely many
possibilities between the apparent factual situation -- that it
supercedes the speed of light -- and that it is indeed instantaneous.
My intuition is that it is not quite instantaneous; however supermodel
theory refrains from saying anything about it, hnf -- hypothesis non
fingo.)
The
other portion
is due to flexibility. And we must regard our view as
privileged and not confused the read-outs of our view with the
measurements portrayed to the empirical physical investigator, with the
filter of HUR involved etc.
Let
me just point
out before we begin to look at the concrete formal
illustrations that people who are not warmed up to the nonlocality
sometimes begin by seeing HUR only as a filter. But the reality is that
HUR is, since measurement is a nonlocal transaction too, both a
question of nonlocality and of being a filter. In getting nonconfused
about this, ie, in having a dialogue of mind and of issues and
questions of matter elaboration so as to elucidate this clearly within
ourselves as a free play of thought and insight, we come to regard
physics as a token of enlightenment and not primarely a tool for
industrial development.
When
we repeat the
illustration, we should expect flexibility to
dictate different results each time. However, if our change is
introduced, we should be able to discern that there is some degree of
symmetry in the immediate change of both particles in the
measurement-like moment. Bell's inequality theorem is about making a
numerical exact prediction of a statistical nature, in terms of a
curve, implying empirical evidence of nonlocality as a feature of
nature as something intrinsically transcending the speed of light, what
Einstein, with some discomfort, referred to as a 'ghostly
action-at-a-distance'. It is my guess that, while Einstein did not
challenge the numerical predictions of quantum theory when he partook
in proposing the EPR thought experiment, he would have been somewhat
surprised by Bell's inequality, which came thirty years later, but
which theoretically could have come the week after (since it built on
nothing except close analysis of the matter at hand, with no
significant reference to empirical discoveries, though with a
motivation at a feeling level from David Bohm's two articles in 1951 on
a hidden variable or 'causal' interpretation of quantum theory).
Let me
further guess that when Bell's analysis had been digested by Einstein,
he would have guessed that an experiment of the kind Aspect did (of an
empirical nature, done some fifteen years later than Bell's analysis,
on exactly this field and with this focus), would come out to the
confirmation of quantum theory. In other words, I do not think Einstein
would have been stubborn in trying to disawow the predictions in
quantum theory once they had been brought out to that level of
precision. But once he had accepted it, he would have had to forgo his
earlier conclusion that the speed of light is conceptually of such
absolute significance; and knowing of Einstein's creativity, he would
have engaged in a radical rethinking of the whole schema, and I think
by and large he would have come up with supermodel theory. Supermodel
theory, it should be noted, gives a lot more credence to general
relativity theory, in that it treats gravitation through curvature and
so on, than several other attempts to incorporate gravitations on a
quantum physical scheme.
With
regard to
Bell's analysis, our illustration (of a formal nature)
is to give a sense of the possible underlaying reality of the case. In
the first and second illustration, the existing type of predictions can
be seen to be reproduced (I say 'type', because the illustration is too
devoid of details to go anywhere near the complexity level required in
the conventional EPR-experiments; but it is quite clear that it has
adequate complexity to give a sense of all the essential conceptual
implications involved). In the third illustration, the issue at hand is
in the area of untested (and hence refutable) predictions.
The
formal
illustrations will now be given with a minimum of
further ado and that completes the physics here. It is effortless to
start up the three programs
on the Green Cat I have made for you on the CDROMs, as a reprogramming
and extension of portions of GNU/Linux Red Hat 8.0, with the program
names supermodel1,
supermodel2 and supermodel3. You will get a view of each moment which
you can rotate, move or scale by simple mouse-clicks or motions, in 3d;
and then you can click NEXT MOMENT in order to see how things develop.
You will see that there is to some extent a real and changable future
to the present manifest moment of each process (as seen for one
observer), and you can take this as a simple illustration of an
infinitely more complex reality along the lines indicated in this book.
Again, I do not wish to say that the formalisation is a formalisation
of the theory, but only of some extracted elements of the theory.
Please keep this in mind, because the theory of supermodels is as such
far greater than any formalisation and only in that way can it be
humble to your own perception, moment by moment, of a living actuality.
With Green Cat, you can make more formalisations so as to explore
these, for instance.
Here follows, pairwise, the six files supermodel1.xml, supermodel1.txt,
supermodel2.xml, supermodel2.txt, supermodel3.xml and finally
supermodel3.txt. The third pair, supermodel3, exemplify refutability:
the initial conditions of the EPR-like situations is not anymore local
contact, but rather a similarity/contrast responding to the Principle
of Movement towards Wholeness. Here, we give only some very simple
indications; in practise, we must of course regard a lot more particles
at the same time with a much more intricate contrast/similarity pattern
(so as to create uniqueness in a world of diversity); and the step from
finding confirmations on this to understanding macroscopic nonlocality
in living young tissue is of course quite big. One of the things which
become easy, though, is that the nonlocality no longer requires
extraordinary conditions to be considered a likely possibility;
although it may be extraordinarily difficult to spot it at first. Once
it is grasped that biological tissue involves patterns repeated over
and over in ways which are unique to each organism, and partially
unique to each specises, and this is seen in the light of a Principle
of Movement towards Wholeness, or PMW, one will see that nonlocality
may be part of the biological finesse in sensitive situations. These
sensitive situations involve a low-noise situation where there is a
great deal of contact between scales of energy, so that there are
series of 'amplifiers' (twoways) between the scales: the macroscopic
level must be sensivity to the microscopic levels and vice versa.
Through the PMW, we can see that this can be part of the meditative
biology of an individual -- this I submit in a refutable sense.
Furthermore, since the nonlocality due to the GRT and QMT is naturally
four-dimensional, not just three-dimensional, the dimension of D for
Duration is involved, and a sense of feedback from possible futures can
be regarded as emitted to the sensitive individual when the brain and
body state is apt for it.
So, though this part of the supermodel theory involves a lot of steps
which I have but sketched here, the essential ingredient is that when
we find a more general condition of nonlocality than in the
conventional QMT, this generality can lend itself for explorations in
all avenues of life. In this sense, the sparks from physics go far,
even into art. Beyond the question of science, we can intend to bring
even economy forth in an organically nonmechanical way as suggested by
an open theory of supermodels or something like that. This infinite
expression of consequences, as paintings, as dance, as poems, must go
beyond any particular thought of reality, any particular theory... but
in going beyond, it is always good to know that we have also had the
opportunity of thinking through some empirics rationally in a way which
is compatible with a nongullible nondogmatic nonviolent open
religiosity or spirituality, which must be the foundation for health at
all levels and in all ways forever. Big words, but deep work can give
such words the right strength of informal open meaning.
<?xml version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8" ?>
<geom>
<geom-off vertices="4" faces="2" node="supermodel1">
<vertices>
<vertex index="0" x="3100000"
y="7100000" z="8100000"/>
<vertex index="1" x="3200000"
y="7200000" z="8200000"/>
<vertex index="2" x="3300000"
y="7300000" z="8300000"/>
<vertex index="3" x="3400000"
y="7400000" z="8400000"/>
</vertices>
<faces>
<face>
<vertices>0
1</vertices>
<color r="1" g="0"
b="0"/>
</face>
<face>
<vertices>2
3</vertices>
<color r="0" g="0"
b="1"/>
</face>
</faces>
</geom-off>
<geom-annotation on="supermodel1" x="2000000" y="2000000"
z="2000000" r="1" g="1" b="0">
<note>Two particles acquire nonlocality due to
local contact</note>
</geom-annotation>
</geom>
( supermodel1.txt )
: supermodel_manifest_moment
( in: movement number / )
this_moment ! this_moment @
dup 1 = if
initialize_std_size_space_duration
3100000 7100000 8100000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
5 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3200000 7200000 8200000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
6 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3300000 7300000 8300000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
7 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3400000 7400000 8400000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
8 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
speedy_direction_right
5 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_right
6 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_left
7 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_left
8 activation_at_this_line
stir_natural_fluctuations
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
5 6 7 8
assert_local_contact_between_two_pairs
activate_PMW
else dup 1 > over 4 < and over 4 > or
if
get_feedback_from_PMW
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
else dup 4 = if
make_measurement_like_influence
7 8 activation_at_these_two_lines
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
then then then
drop ;
<?xml version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8" ?>
<geom>
<geom-off vertices="4" faces="2" node="supermodel2">
<vertices>
<vertex index="0" x="3100000"
y="7100000" z="8100000"/>
<vertex index="1" x="3200000"
y="7200000" z="8200000"/>
<vertex index="2" x="3300000"
y="7300000" z="8300000"/>
<vertex index="3" x="3400000"
y="7400000" z="8400000"/>
</vertices>
<faces>
<face>
<vertices>0
1</vertices>
<color r="1" g="0"
b="0"/>
</face>
<face>
<vertices>2
3</vertices>
<color r="0" g="0"
b="1"/>
</face>
</faces>
</geom-off>
<geom-annotation on="supermodel2" x="2000000" y="2000000"
z="2000000" r="1" g="1" b="0">
<note>An EPR-like situation with curvature,
effortlessly implemented</note>
</geom-annotation>
</geom>
( supermodel2.txt also by s.v.r. )
: supermodel_manifest_moment
( in: movement number / )
this_moment ! this_moment @
dup 1 = if
initialize_std_size_space_duration
3100000 7100000 8100000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
5 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3200000 7200000 8200000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
6 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3300000 7300000 8300000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
7 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3400000 7400000 8400000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
8 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
speedy_direction_right
5 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_right
6 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_left
7 activation_at_this_line
speedy_direction_left
8 activation_at_this_line
stir_natural_fluctuations
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
5 6 7 8
assert_local_contact_between_two_pairs
activate_PMW
4200000 6200000 7200000
assert_std_singularity_curvature_centered_here
else dup 1 > over 4 < and over 4 > or
if
get_feedback_from_PMW
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
else dup 4 = if
make_measurement_like_influence
7 8 activation_at_these_two_lines
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
then then then
drop ;
<?xml version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8" ?>
<geom>
<geom-off vertices="4" faces="2" node="supermodel3">
<vertices>
<vertex index="0" x="3000000"
y="8000000" z="9000000"/>
<vertex index="1" x="3200000"
y="8200000" z="9200000"/>
<vertex index="2" x="4000000"
y="6000000" z="7000000"/>
<vertex index="3" x="4200000"
y="6200000" z="7200000"/>
</vertices>
<faces>
<face>
<vertices>0
1</vertices>
<color r="1" g="0"
b="0"/>
</face>
<face>
<vertices>2
3</vertices>
<color r="0" g="0"
b="1"/>
</face>
</faces>
</geom-off>
<geom-annotation on="supermodel3" x="2000000" y="2000000"
z="2000000" r="1" g="1" b="0">
<note>Two particles acquire nonlocality due to
similar contrasts</note>
</geom-annotation>
</geom>
( supermodel3.txt by stein von reusch )
( this manhattan forth creates 3d simulation in green cat )
( in a rather self-explanatory fashion given the physics chapter )
( in the book, which also lists this source )
( my forth definitions for manhattan are included with full source on
CDs )
( which relate Charles Moore's Forth to XML/3d by Daeron Meyer )
( in the novel work done for this book, PASSION )
( a commentary in Forth is a parenthesis on a line like this )
( Forth is explained in many free and open texts )
( and in the excellent book Starting Forth by Leo Brodie )
( program structure for supermodel3: )
( initialize the )
( supermodel called SPACE_DURATION )
( set it up with similar energy )
( frequency for two particles moving )
( in opposing directions )
( the first xml has these two particles )
( and nothing else )
( links from SPACE_DURATION to )
( xml are established with regard )
( to its changeable structures )
( program info on supermodel2.txt )
( if everything is made of )
( photon-like excitations, )
( and each of these proceeds )
( in a standard speed )
( -- with fluctuating or circular )
( direction changes to give an )
( appearance of slowness )
( it follows that if the area )
( though which they proceed on is )
( stretched, the internal processes )
( will slow down -- the curvature )
( is such stretching)
( in the formalism, )
( the standard movement )
( speed, or C, is set )
( to be five nodes )
( pr moment )
( this is )
( not an ontological proposal )
( ie, it could be fifty )
( if phenomena of nonlocality )
( can in general be seen )
( to be emergent out of a )
( principle of movement toward wholeness )
( which has boundless contrast and )
( similarity detection features, then by )
( virtue of this boundlessness, in SPACE_DURATION, )
( nonlocality would be expected to be pervasive; )
( and in situations of sensitivity of )
( macroscopic processes to finer and finer levels, )
( macroscopic nonlocality would be the )
( potential (so also for brain structure, )
( body etc)
( to illustrate other aspects of )
( the supermodel theory, such as )
( warp / tunneling or more GRT or QMT )
( features, the formalism must be )
( extended somewhat -- for instance, )
( a warp flag should be a movement )
( option for each particle, with a )
( supermodel carrying out the process. )
( however, any further use of formalism )
( may lead to new kinds of bombs etc )
( and it is something which is the )
( responsibility of anyone developing )
( this formalism further, )
( it is not my responsibility )
( here, we put the uncertainty )
( relation to nonlocal interaction )
( between a measurement apparatus )
( and the measured structure, not to )
( the PW in itself on its own; but )
( uncertainty or openness in itself )
( characterises all supermodels, )
( of course; so then the earlier )
( statement on representing position )
( vs tendency is NOT essential; )
( however I feel that the earlier )
( is also a valid perspective )
( square the vector given by )
( the x, y of the "curvature" )
( two-dimensionality of PW )
( supermodels )
( give the highest relative )
( x, y, z, d through coded )
( minimum-curvature to each )
( particle, such that )
( 00,00,00,00 under zero )
( is x,y,z,d and std curvature )
( is 1000 )
( the PMW is the place where )
( E=hf excells )
: supermodel_manifest_moment
( in: movement number / )
this_moment ! this_moment @
dup 1 = if
initialize_std_size_space_duration
3000000 8000000 9000000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
5 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
3200000 8200000 9200000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
6 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
4000000 6000000 7000000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
7 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
4200000 6200000 7200000
std_minimum_activation_frequency
8 already_mapped_in_xml_at_this_line
( now the xml is mapped to the )
( curvature and the curvature )
( is standardized although of course )
( having flexibility as everything )
( else with supermodels )
std_direction_right
5 activation_at_this_line
std_direction_right
6 activation_at_this_line
std_direction_left
7 activation_at_this_line
std_direction_left
8 activation_at_this_line
stir_natural_fluctuations
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
activate_PMW
else dup 1 > over 6 < and over 6 > or
if
get_feedback_from_PMW
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
else dup 6 = if
make_measurement_like_influence
7 8 activation_at_these_two_lines
stir_natural_fluctuations
act_out_results_of_feedback_from_PMW_etc
perpetuate_this_moment_into_open_future
do_more_PMW
convert_this_moment_to_XML_and_usher_it_to_rendering
then then then
drop ;
BEGINNINGS
This book is beginnings...
To excell in any area requires a love for this area, a love for
excellence, a willingness to set aside all plans, all deliberations,
all prejudice, and just go for it. It also requires a willingness to
trust organic sensitivity, openness and fluctuations, and not insist on
some scheme or ideal if the heart says that it is right. Christian
Krogh, one of the grand old men at the time that Edward Munch were up
and coming as a young painter in Norway, initially wrote: I do not find
that the paintings of Munch are finished. Then, after some years, he
generously added: But when the heart of an artist says, this is what I
wanted to express, then a painting is finished after all, are they not?
Well, I am not sure what Munch's heart said about Munch's paintings,
but my heart tells me: this book is finished. It is what it is, with
all its word variations, (socalled 'spelling mistakes'), its openness
(socalled 'contradictions') and its freedom (socalled 'confusions').
Let it be what it is! Let it be reprinted! It is the FIRST AND FINAL
edition for I wish to go to the oral stage and give talks and entertain
delightful conversations, to walk far and journey much, paint much and
dance and do yoga too, alone and with the gorgeous dancers, tantrically
and artistically, the girls that turn my mind on...