de Broglie vs Bohm
--authentic quotes from Louis de Broglie,
forefather of a portion of the original quantum theory,
on how his revised (nonlocal) pilot wave theory
diverges from what is today called bohmian mechanics
SCROLL AHEAD TO PHOTOS OF BOOK
TO READ DE BROGLIE, 1956, ON BOHM
If it is true that de Broglie helped Bohm,
and that Bohm helped de Broglie,
it's also true that we have here two,
not just one, branches of nonlocal pilot
wave versions of quantum physics,
when it comes to pictures of eg the
particle and the wave. Here's a
quick walk-through of what de Broglie
wanted to visualize of quantum phenomena,
after his own words have been quoted.
This is the first time this particular
series of comments by Nobel laurate and
one of the topmost physicists in the 20th
century, Louis de Broglie, have been made
easily available on the internet.
For physicists who are groomed in a
tradition that is sceptical to the
importance of this interpretation:
remember that when we look aside
from which theory came first,
then, for any set of theories predicting
the same type of things (so far),
we must apply other criterions than
'does it predict something new'.
Among these: elegance; a sense of
wholeness as regards other plausble
theories; intuitiveness. And this is
a question not of dogma, but of letting
science, in the best spirit of both
being sceptical and open-minded,
look calmly at alternatives.
Note: in the comments before and after
the verbatim quotes from de Broglie's
hugely interesting and well-written
1956 book (from the translated 1960
publication by Elsevier Co. Pub.),
we use the phrase 'pilot wave theory'
(or pilot-wave theory) to cover a
broad range of theories. In de Broglie's
own vocabulary, the pilot-wave theory
was a watered-down version of a grander
theory that he called the Double Solution.
Our comments are in agreement with common
word usage, in which we regard any theory
that attributes such as both position and
momentum to particles at all times together
with some form of nonlocal guiding wave or
field to account for quantum phenomena,
as a pilot wave theory or interpretation.
Quotes occupying a few pages of a book
of some 300 pages are here given, and,
to further honor the copyright to the
Louis de Broglie foundation of all the
texts of Louis de Broglie, neither
complete footnotes nor complete proof-
reading of this typed-in document is
provided. The typing-in was completed
in June 2016, and after this point, only
the LINKS section, with link to the
World Wide Web for further reading and
to the catalogue numbers of the books
and articles most referred to, will be
updated, to accomodate changes on the web.
USE THIS FOR PRIVATE EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES.
This is put forth in a benefit-for-all
spirit and not intended for commercial
use nor for mass-reproduction in a
different medium. Please retain this
document as a whole if you make a private
backup of it. --SRW
Excerpts provided in June, 2016 by S.R. Weber.
Link section at the completion of this
document by intent updated yearly.
SHORTEST POSSIBLE SUMMARY
Across the world most physicists are now appreciating
the consistency of an alternative form of quantum theory
to the mainstream version due to, among others, N.Bohr
and W.Heisenberg, which is called, for instance,
bohmian mechanics, and also, the de Broglie/Bohm pilot
wave theory or interpretation. However, de Broglie came
with two pilot wave theories--one, in the 1920s, which
David Bohm rediscovered in the early 1950s and improved
upon, so that it became consistent. And a second, in the
1950s, which is due to the revision that Louis de Broglie
himself undertook of his own theory after reading Bohm's
work and responding very positive to parts of what Bohm
had done. Louis de Broglie, Nobel laurate and one of the
great forefathers of all quantum theory, profoundly
disagreed with Bohm at one key point, at least. A few
physicists have published articles on this point. Most
have no inkling about this difference at all. In this
page, yoga6d.org/debroglie_vs_bohm, the source material
is all available at the fingertips for anyone to study
further on their own. This then, is to remedy what may
be of importance for future physics studies of the pilot
wave type of theories, esp. now that, in the past couple
of years, this type of interpretation has begun to receive
some empirical support, and renewed praised from mainstream
science journals and magazines.
BACKGROUND
Most people who have studied quantum theory know that,
among the major interpretations, bohmian mechanics is
one of them. This is also called the de Broglie/Bohm
theory, because of the ideas Louis de Broglie put forward
in the 1920s, and which, in part, Bohm rediscovered and
improved upon in his own theory in the early 1950s.
While there is no doubt that Louis de Broglie read and
enjoyed and found it beneficial the work that David Bohm
had done, and built on it, and that, in turn, David Bohm
and his colleges also read Louis de Broglie and benefitted
from his work, including his use of metaphors, it is, at
the time of writing this (2016), only a few voices in the
physics community who suggest that de Broglie's pilot wave
theory is, in fact, a different theory than that of David
Bohm causal or, as he later preferred, ontological
interpretation.
As I had the great joy of meeting David Bohm and his wife
Sarel several times (before I adopted the pen name SRWeber;
they knew me as Henning Braten), I could have asked him about
these things when I had the chance. As it is, it was only by
chance, many years after Bohm's death, that I came across
the book by Louis de Broglie on the matter, where he
refers in detail, and graciously, to Bohm's work, while
at the same time spelling out how his view of reality is
at several interesting points absolutely different. I
recalled then that a physicist at the University of
Bristol, years, earlier, had pointed it out to me, that
these two theories are indeed distinct. As I indicated,
but very few physicists have as yet worked on this
distinction (a notable exception is the work of A.Valentini,
who however has also worked on his own version of pilot wave
theory along entirely different lines than that which
de Broglie proposed). While in 2016 what I here set forth
is not at all common knowledge, I should hope that within
some years, the internet flourishes not only with
descriptions of "de Broglie/Bohm" theory, but also with
descriptions of the unique features of the de Broglie
theory of the 1950s as compared to the theory due to
David Bohm and the further developments by B.Hiley,
C.Dewdney, A.Steinberg and the many others who have now,
across the world, taken up the pilot wave theory in one
form or another and begun seeing it as a serious
alternative to the Bohr/Heisenberg interpretation of
quantum phenomena. All these developments can be
mutually fruitful when we give space to each one of them
in a caring scientific philosophical light without the
needless emotionality that sometimes characterises the
socalled 'scientific discourse'. This is not about voting
in favour or against Bohm, but rather trying to honor the
role of the human mind in a first-hand sense doing
informal visualisations of reality as whole, when we also
engage in precise formalisations of parts of these
visualisations and compare the predictions that may
arise from some of these formalisations when bridged,
by additional assumptions, to some empirical domains.
Bohm has opened some doors, but as I see it, the work on
rethinking physics has barely begun.
Many people seem to regard Bohm's work as the fulfillment of
that which de Broglie started. However, what is the case
is that though the formalism at some levels are identical,
the theory of reality is, indeed, a very different one.
And in these days, when empirical studies, such as by
A.Goldberg, are beginning to arise to as to compare the
mainstream interpretation of Bohr and Heiseberg against
bohmian mechanics, and where one might surmise that physicists
might soon be able to formulate at least slightly different
predictions in some realms involving nonlocality so as to
check one interpretation against another (supposing, for
instance, that a physicist undertood to reformulate a part
of bohmian mechanics), it may be of value to actually
consider what Louis de Broglie himself said on the matter.
After extensively researching all available fully public
internet sites referring to Louis de Broglie, I have found
that essential points of de Broglie are neither presented
in original form nor in a properly re-presented form by
others and have undertaken to remedy this by creating this
page. This document is, I hope, clear enough even though
it is not proofread--neither my own comments nor
the quotes or excerpts from the important 1956 book of
Louis de Broglie, where he disassociates himself from an
'easy' pilot wave interpretation and goes in for a more
'heavy' pilot wave interpretation, in contradistinction
to what I perceive is most of the works of David Bohm
on this matter. Louis de Broglie being who he is, means
that we should consider again whether he has all the time
harbored a 'better' pilot wave theory hidden under his
(rather private) heading of 'The Double Solution'.
AS FOR COPYRIGHTS: The de Broglie quotes are here given in
a purely educational spirit and you find in the links
section also links to the copyright holders of all
published material of Louis de Broglie, and these must be
consulted for any further use of this material. While the
quotes are somewhat longer than that which is typical of
a book not yet fully released in the public domain, it is
after all only a fraction of the book that is here, and
only the text part, not the equations, and as it will help
the cause of understanding the brilliant thinking of Louis
de Broglie it will probably only help the cause of the
copyright holders that these excerpts of the 1960
translation are given here.
Before we go on, let me say that David Bohm read and
referred to de Broglie's 1950s work. But Bohm emphasized
the points of connection and agreement, and he also found
it fruitful to bring further a metaphor over the particle
that de Broglie proposed. This is understandable in a
context where Bohm's work had been rediculed instead of
researched upon for years, until J.S.Bell began to clear
up how Bohm had been able to do something that most
physicists at the time regarded as 'proven impossible',
due to deduction by J.v.Neumann in the 1920s. Bohm, finding
a degree of support in de Broglie's work, naturally
emphasized this support, seeing that it came from a very
important character in the scientific community. However,
what with a number of physicists now regarding bohmian
mechanics as a viable alternative, in some respects, to
the Copenhagen Interpretation, and philosophers such as
H.Putnam has, in 2005 [in Brit.J.Phil.Sci., 56:615-634], called
pilot wave theory quite 'elegant', we are in a situation
where it would be interesting to refine variations of these
various interpretations so as to suggest possible
differences in empirical predictions. And in order to
give full credit to the full range of possibilities in
so doing, we should pay outmost attention to the fact that
while Bohm's equations and de Broglie's equations are, on
the surface, the same, de Broglie has a wholly different
picture of reality. In this different picture, one is led
to think differently about particles and waves than how
it is done in bohmian mechanics. For a clear-headed
empiricial physicist with a good grasp of the ideas
involved, this may suggest entirely different ways of
going about it to do such as to pinpoint the tracks of
particles or the possible reality of the pilot wave.
Indeed, one can surmise that within some decades, there
may be different 'renditions' of pilot wave theory, some
more in tune with Bohm, some more in tune with de Broglie,
some bringing in new concepts altogether, all of which
lends themselves to suggest slightly or possibly very
different empirical predictions in exceptional quantum-
physical experiments of a type not yet encountered. I have
my own work, my own more informal theory of the whole,
which I call "super-model theory", and naturally hope
that this will also receive the attention it deserves
in due course. This, by the way, leans more on de Broglie's
pilot wave theory than on bohmian mechanics, but brings
in several new concepts to relate to such as quantum
biology (I'm working on a new presentation of this
theory these months and will, when it is done, present
a book in .pdf form at the following location:
yoga6d.org/super-model-theory -- but by June 2016 this
has not been finished yet).
Be sure to look at the link section at the
completion of this page. This link section will be
checked about yearly and updated moderately. Louis de
Broglie wrote an article in French on the same themes
that he develops rather more deeply in the 1956 book,
a couple of years before he wrote that book. This article
has been translated and with the permission of the Louis
de Broglie Foundation, been submitted to the public
domain, and is the first of the links given underneath
the quotes from the book.
After the quotes, we will briefly summarize, in a
slightly updated language, what Louis de Broglie actually
stated as to the difference.
Another point of interest: if you look at the developments
in modern physics incl. quantum theory from about 1960 to
now, in this half-century and more, most of the general
thoughts about quantum theory and indeed also, most of
the questions raised by Louis de Broglie, could more or
less be written today, with the exception of many footnotes
added as to variations of equations and efforts to do such
as to get the dependency on measurements away from quantum
theory, and additional mentioning of such as many-worlds
interpretations and so on. And the status of Einstein's
theories are, if anything, more confirmed than ever; and
there are, of course, many new formal results where additional
bridges between his type of theories and forms of quantum
field theory, and such, have been erected, but these things
are chiefly in the terreign of formalistic achievements. Also,
the presence of lists of quarks and other assumedly fundamental
particles alongside a set of equations do not postulate a
new philosophical grip on the situation, as much as a
systematization of a range of new empirical results largely
within the worldview as chiselled out in those early days.
As a result, the question of interpretation of quantum
phenomena is, if anything, as hot as ever.
PHOTOS OF THE 1956 BOOK AND THE 1960 ENGLISH TRANSLATION
EXCERPTS FROM THE ENGLISH TRANSLATION OF THE 1956 BOOK
Note: the link to the worldcatalogue id of the 1960
translation copyright Elsevier Publishing Company
is given in the link section at the completion. The
copyright holders for Louis de Broglie material in
general is the de Broglie Foundation where contact info
is given in link 3.
The following excerpts are for private educational purposes.
For any mass or commercial distribution, please contact
copyright holders as given in the link section first.
All following quotes are from Non-Linear Wave Mechanics,
A Causal Interpretation by Louis de Broglie, transl. by
Arthur J. Knodel and Jack C. Miller, Amsterdam, 1960,
Elsevier Publishing Company, Library of Congress Catalog
Card Number 59-12588. The page numbers refer to the
hardcover (1st) edition. This is a translation from Une
Tentative D'interpretation Causale et Non Linaire de
La Mecanique Ondulatoire (La Theorie de la Double
Solution) by Louis de Broglie, Gauthier-Villars, Paris, 1956.
Confer, as said, the link section for the worldcat.org page
for this book.
There are, in de Broglie's book, a few reference to numbered
bibliographical references and to footnotes underneath some
of the pages; for simplicity, these are here not included;
please consider getting the whole book (292 pages plus
appendix etc) to study also these.
Textual translation points:
Only text, not equations, are included. The greek letter named Psi,
when mentioned inside the prose text of de Broglie, is here written
as "Psi", rather than by the greek character, so that what follows is
an ascii-text-friendly set of excerpts; italics are shown _as this_,
which is typical also in eg. www.gutenberg.org texts. [Indeed, it
would be fruitful if the de Broglie Foundation contacts gutenberg.org
and submits to them the book in full, both in its French original
form and in the form of the English translation, in agreement
with Elsevier, for there is material here of vital importance for
the education of the scientists and thinkers of the future.]
A couple of places de Broglie utilises, in the midst of prose
text, something that requires such as an elevated small font,
and then we have improvised a notation like [RAISED TO] to
indicate this textual phenomenon, but it is fairly obvious the
few places it arises. The book itself is dense with equations,
but we regard the chief points to come forth in the text.
[Any grammatical and spelling errors are due to the typing-in
process, and probably not at all in the original 1960 book.]
ORIGINAL QUOTES FROM LOUIS DE BROGLIE'S
1956 BOOK IN THE 1960 TRANSLATION
From PREFACE:
[..]
As early as 1923 I had clearly seen that the propagation of a wave
must be associated with the movement of every particle, but the
continous wave--of the type familiar in Classical Optics--which
I had been led to consider and which became the Psi wave of ordinary
Wave Mechanics, did not seem to me to describe the physical reality
accurately; only its _phase_, related direclty to the motion of the particle,
seemed to me of fundamental significance, and that is why I had
named the wave which I associated with the particle "the phase-
wave"--a designation that is completely forgotten today, but which
at that time I believed entirely justified. However, as the work of
other scientists led to further progress in Wave Mechanics, it became
daily more evident that the Psi wave with its continous amplitude
could be used only in statistical predictions. And so, little by little,
there was an increasing trend towards the "purely probabilistic"
interpretation, of which Born, Bohr and Heisenberg were the chief
advocates. I was surprised at this development, which did not seem
to me to fulfill the "explanatory" aim of theoretical physics; and that
is what led me, around 1925-1927, to believe that all problems
of Wave Mechanics required a set of two coupled solutions of the
wave equation: one, the Psi wave, definite in phase, but, because of the
continous character of its amplitude, having only a statistical and
subjective meaning; the other, the u wave of the same phase as the Psi
wave but with an amplitude having very large values around a point in
space and which, precisely on account of its spatial singularity
(a singularity, moreover, which may not be one in the strict mathe-
matical sense of the term) can be used to describe the particle ob-
jectively. In this way I obtained, in agreement with Einstein's concepts,
what I had always believed must be sought: a picture of the particle
in which it appears as the center of an extended wave phenomenon
involving the particle in an intimate way. And, thanks to the theo-
retically postulated parallelism between u and Psi waves, the Psi wave,
it seemed to me, preserved all the statistical properties that had quite
rightly been attributed to it. [..] [..] I should like this line of
thought, abandoned for some twenty-five years now and believed to
lead to an impasse, to be carefully re-examined to see whether, on
the contrary, it may not be the pathway that might lead to the true
Microphysics of the Future.
Chapter I. The basic ideas of wave mechanics
From page 3:
1. Point of departure
The idea which, in my 1923-1924 works, served as the point of
departure for Wave Mechanics was the following: Since for light there
exists a corpuscular aspect and a wave aspect united by the relation-
ship Energy = h times frequency, where h, Planck's constant, enters
in, it is natural to suppose that, the matter as well, there exists a cor-
poscular _and_ a wave aspect, the latter having been hitherto unrecog-
nised.
Chapter III. First principles relative to the probabilistic
interpretations of Psi waves
From page 29:
1. The central problem in the interpretation of Wave Mechanics
From the very beginnings of the study of Wave Mechanics, the
problem of the exact significance to be attributed to the Psi wave was
seen to be fraught with great difficulties. It was immediately apparent
that it was not possible to consider the Psi function as a physical quan-
tity in the old sense--for example, as representing the vibration of
some medium. [..]
For [..] particle systems, the Psi wave is propagated in a configura-
tion space, which is an abstract and fictitious space.
The more the formalism of employing the Psi wave became apparent,
the more it appeared as a kind of formal and subjective representation
making possible the evaluation of the probabilities of certain results of
measurement. We will have occasion to show in the course of studying
this probabilistic interpretation of the Psi function that this wave-func-
tion, defined in the usual fashion as a solution of the linear equations
of propagation mentioned in the preceeding chapter, can by no means
be considered an objective reality, but only as an element having the
same subjective qualities as the probabilities it represents, an element
suspectible to variations dependent upon the knowledge of the person
employing it.
The overriding question, then, is to find out whether the probabil-
istic interpretation of the Psi wave, which unquestionably leads to
exact predictions, constitutes a "complete" representation beyond
which there is no point in seeking an objective description of reality, or
whether, on the contrary, the description of phenomena by the ex-
clusive use of the Psi wave is "incomplete" and must make room for a
more profound and detailed description of physical reality. We will
have occasion to return more than once to this problem.
From page 48:
5. Remarks on the Wave Mechanics of systems of particles
[..]
Schroedinger's idea of identifying the Psi wave of a system in con-
figuration space at first shocked me very greatly, because, configura-
tion space being a pure fiction, this conception deprives the Psi wave of
all physical reality. For me the wave of Wave Mechanics should have
evolved in three-dimensional physical space. [..]
The [..] Psi wave in configuration space [..] is a purely imaginary
way of representing wave phenomena which, in point of fact, take place
in physical space.
Chapter VI. Various aspects of the probabalistic
interpretation of wave mechanics
From page 63:
4. The notion of complementarity (Bohr)
[..]
The idea of complementary, although a bit elusive, is an interesting
one. Attempts have been made to apply it in various fields--a pro-
cedure that is not always entirely safe. But, from the fact that measur-
ing processes do not permit us to assign a position and a state of motion
simultaneously to a particle, are we necessarily obliged to conclude
that, in reality, the particle has _neither position nor velocity_?
From page 70:
7. Von Neumann's theorem
[..]
The examination of this question led me--and on this point I am in
agreement with David Bohm--to think that von Neumann's dem-
onstration implies a hypothesis that is not absolutely unavoidable [..].
Chapter VII. Objections to the purely probabalistic
interpretation of wave mechanics
From pages 74-79:
2. Einstein's objection at the 1927 Solvay Congress
At the Solvay Congress of October 1927, Einstein raised a very
striking objection to the purely probabalistic interpretation of Wave
Mechanics.
[..]
In Einstein's example, the particle would in a sense be spread out in
a virtual state in the space beyond the screen. At the moment an effect
localized at A takes place, the particle would, so to speak, condense at
that point in order to produce an observable phenomenon. [..]
It is thus legitimate to consider Einstein's example as a very serious
objection to the present interpretation of Wave Mechanics--one that
has never been clearly answered.
3. The example of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen
There have been lively and interesting discussions, in which very
eminent scientists have participated, on the subject of "correlated"
systems, that is, of systems which, once having been in interaction
find themselves subsequently separated from each other, but in states
with probabilities that are no longer independent.
[..]
Bohr's reasoning, on occasion rather nebulous, contains a number
of questionable assertions. [..]
Chapter VIII. Introduction and program
From pages 89-91:
1. History of the theory of the Double Solution
[..]
So I boldly laid down a hypothesis--that of the Double Solution--
according to which the linear equations of Wave Mechanics admitted
two kinds of solution: the continuous Psi solutions one normally thinks
of--the statistical nature of which was beginning to come clearly
apparent at that time, thanks to the work of Born, and "singularity"
solutions that would have a concrete meaning and be the true physical
representation of the wave-particle dualism. Particles would then be
_incorporated_ in an extended wave phenomenon. For this reason, the
motion of a particle would not obey the laws of Classical Mechanics
according to which the particle is subject only to the actions of forces
exerted on it in the course of its trajectory, without experiencing any
effect from the existence of obstacles that may be situated at some
distance outside the trajectory. In my conception, on the contrary, the
motion of the singularity was to be dependent on all the obstacles that
hindred the free propagation of the wave phenomenon surrounding it,
and there would result from this a reaction of the wave phenomenon
on the particle--a reaction expressed in my theory by the appearance
of a "quantum potential" entirely different from the potential of
ordinary foces. And in this way the appearance of interference and
diffraction phenomena would be explained.
Unfortunately the development of this theory of the Double Solution
presented great mathematical difficulties. For that reason, when I was
requested to present a paper on Wave Mechanics at the Solvay Physi-
cal Congress held in Brussels in October 1927, I contented myself with a
presentation of my ideas in an incomplete and dilluted form which I
called the "pilot-wave theory". [..]
And I used the term "pilot-wave theory" for the theory limited to the
postulation of the existence of the particle and the Psi wave, with no
further reference to a wave containing a singularity. This watered-
down version of my original conception happened to coincide exactly
with the one put forward at the same date by Madelung in his hydro-
dynamical interpretation of Wave Mechanics, but this simplified ver-
sion had far less interest and profundity than my initial ideas on the
Double Solution. My presentation at the Solvey Congress was received
unfavorably, and the purely probabalistic interpretation of Bohr, Born
and Heisenberg supported by Pauli, Dirac and others, was very clearly
the one preferred by most of the scientists present.
[..]
On the other hand, my original theory of the Double Solution, by
distinguishing the Psi wave, with its probabalistic and subjective char-
acter, from the singularity-wave (u wave), which was to be a de-
scription of objective reality, might possibly supply the more classical
type of interpretation I was after. But I knew only too well that the
theory of the double solution likewise involved numerous difficulties,
especially when it came to the existence and form of singularity-waves
and to their relation to the Psi waves, or when one had to interpret in
terms of singularity-waves interference experiments of the Young-slit
type, etc.
Confronted with all these difficulties, I gave up these attempts, for
their outcome struck me as far too problematical. From 1928 on I
embraced Bohr's probabalistic interpretation as the basis of my per-
sonal research, my teaching and my books.
During the summer of 1951, there came to my attention, much to my
surprise, a paper by David Bohm which appeared subsequently in
The Physical Review. In this paper Bohm went back to my theory
of the pilot-wave, considering the Psi wave as a physical reality. He
made a certain number of interesting remarks on the subject, and in
particular, he indicated the broad outline of a theory of measurement
that seemed to answer the objections Pauli had made to my approach
in 1927. My first reaction on reading Bohm's work was to reiterate [..]
the objections [..] [..]. Takabayasi, moreover, subsequently took up
these objections in papers where he developed aspects of Bohm's theory
in an interesting way.
Chapter IX. Principles on the theory of the double solution
From page 111:
8. The guidance formula and the theory of the pilot-wave
[..]
If there exists--as the theory of the Double Solution assumes--an ob-
jective wave phenomenon represented by a wave u, having a singular
region, whose propagation is modified by the action of external fields
and by the presence of obstacles (interference and diffraction), one can
then conceive that everything takes place as if the trajectory of the
particle, which is really imposed upon it by the propagation of the u
wave, were determined by the phase of the Psi wave. But it is impossible
to assume that it is the Psi wave that regulates the motion of the par-
icle because this Psi wave is only a probability representation with a
fictious and subjective character.
We will be obliged to return repeatedly to this important question.
We will see especially that, in his paper of January 1952, David Bohm
has again taken up the theory of the pilot-wave, assuming that the
Psi wave is a "physical reality". This point of view seems inadmissable
to me, even when we are concerned with the noramlized Psi wave of
Wave Mechanics for a single particle, and then, all the more so when it
is a matter of the Psi wave of a system of particles in configuration space.
From page 172-173:
4. Supplementary observations
The principle of Bohm's demonstration consists of pointing out that
the Psi wave of a particle or of a system is always slightly perturbed by
the existence of very small external actions (weak collisions, for ex-
ample) and of assuming that these small perturbing potentials repre-
sent these actions with their entirely random fluctuations. It is here a
question of potentials of a classic type, but Vigier has quite correct-
ly pointed out that one could consider small perturbing quantum po-
tentials resulting from small random fluctuations in boundary condi-
tions (for example, the thermal motion of the walls of a receptacle).
[..]
It is curious to note that in this way there would be achieved a
synthesis of the conceptions of the causal theory and of Einstein's
frequently reiterated affirmation that the successes of the statistical
interpretation of Wave Mechanics imply underlying particle-movements
of a Brownian character.
[A footnote on page 173; SQUARE is our rendering of the elevated 2:]
Since 1954, when this passage was written, I have come to support
wholeheartedly an hypothesis proposed by Bohm and Vigier. According
to this hypothesis, the random perturbations to which the particle
would be constantly subjected, and which would have the probability
of presence in terms of SQUARE [ |Psi| ], arise from the interaction
of the particle with a "subquantic medium" which escapes our
observations and is entirely chaotic, and which is everywhere
present in what we call "empty space".
From page 175:
Chapter XIV. Pauli's objections to the theory of the pilot-wave
1. The discussion of the pilot-wave theory at the Solvay Congress
of October 1927
[..]
However, when I was asked to present a paper on Wave Mechanics
at the Solvay Congress that was to be held in Brussels during October
1927, I balked at the difficulties in mathematically justifying the
double-solution point of view, and I contented myself with a presenta-
ion of the pilot-wave point of view. At the Solvay Congress, while a
few of the "old guard" (Lorentz, Einstein, Langevin, Schroedinger)
insisted on the necessity of finding a causal interpretation of Wave
Mechanics--without, however, coming out in favor of my efforts--
Bohr and Born, along with their young disciples (Heisenberg, Dirac,
etc.), came out categorically in favor of the new purely probabalistic
interpretation that they had developed, and they did not even discuss
my point of view. Pauli was the only one to present a definite objection
to my theory, and he did so by examining the case of a collision between
a particle and a rotator, which Fermi had studied a short while before.
[..]
From page 182:
3. Pauli's objection to the guidance formula
[..]
So I had perceived, as the quotation given above shows, that the
answer to Pauli's objection would have to rely on the fact that the
wave-trains are always limited. And this idea has been taken up again
by Bohm in his recent Papers.
From pages 183-185:
4. The abandonment of attempts of a causal interpretation
of Wave Mechanics after 1927
In the months that followed the Solvay Congress of October 1927,
I abandoned the pilot-wave approach that I had maintained. But not
because of Pauli's objection. For, as I say, I thought I had found the
way in which to overcome it. Rather, I abandoned the pilot-wave ap-
proach for other, more general, reasons. [..] A summary of these
reasons follows.
The particle, conceived as a physical reality, cannot, I said to myself,
be guided by the Psi wave, whose probability-representational character
(at once subjective and conditioned by the knowledge of its user) had
been plained revealed by the development of Wave Mechanics.
This fictitious character of the Psi wave was already forced upon us
for the Psi wave associated with only a single particle in ordinary space.
It thus became all the more inescapable in the case of the Psi wave of a
system, which is propgated in the system's configuration space, which
is purely abstract.
[..]
Such were the considerations that led me, in 1928, to abandon the
pilot-wave theory as untenable. The original form of my ideas, _i.e._ the
theory of the Double Solution, did not seem to me to run into the same
difficulties, but I had become convinced that its mathematical justi-
fiction, if it were possible, was beyond my capacities.
[..]
And then in January 1952 appeared the two Papers by David Bohm.
We will now analyze the main arguments of these two Papers.
From pages 186-187:
Chapter XV. Bohm's theory of measurement and the statistical
schema of the causal theory
1. Bohm's papers of January 1952
The two articles published simultaneously by David Bohm in
January 1952 in _The Physical Review_ once more focussed attention
on the question of the interpretation of Wave Mechanics. In these pa-
paers Bohm reverts to the pilot-wave theory in the form I had given to
it at the 1927 Solvay Congress. He assumes that the Psi wave is a
physical reality (even the Psi wave in configuration space!). I have
already stated why such an hypothesis appeared absolutely untenable
to me.
[..]
Bohm's papers contain still other statements that strike us as du-
bious. For example, he is undoubtably right in saying that on a very
reduced scale (10 [RAISED TO]-13 cm or less the guidance formula, and
consequently the staistical significance of the Psi, could very well
no longer hold, but the modification of the equation of propagation
which he proposes as a remedy seems to me artificial.
Nevertheless, if Bohm's work calls for certain reservations, it also
has merits that seem to me unquestionable. In particular, he has once
more focussed attention on the possibility of the an interpretation of Wave
Mechanics different from the one that is now prevalent, and he has
shown that it is not pointless to submit the whole question to a pains-
taking re-examination.
[..]
These are a few of the interesting results developed by Bohm in his
two papers, but the most original part of his work is certainly his
theory of measurement, which we are now going to analyse.
From page 188:
2. The theory of measurement according to Bohm
[..]
This study of interaction led Bohm to analyze measuring
processes which, by and large, amount to the interaction of a particle
and a measuring apparatus (pp. 179-184 of the second paper). The
performance of the measurement establishes "correlations" between
the particle's final state and the final state of the measuring apparatus,
so that the observation of the final state of the apparatus permits us to
deduce the final state of the particle.
From page 193:
[..]
From the point of view adopted here, every quantity Q of the par-
ticle has a well defined value in its initial state, but this value is a
"hidden variable", since, generally, every attempt at measuring it will
result in its modification. If by some exception a measuring apparatus
does allow us to obtain a value of Q without modification, then that
apparatus will modify the values of all the quantities P that do not
commute with Q.
So we must carefully distinguish between the "hidden variables"--
which in the causal theory as well as in Classical Physics, would at
every instant characterize the particle's position and motion--and the
"observables" in Dirac's sense, which are the values of these quantities
obtainable by a measuring operation. This shows, in accordance with
certain ideas of Bohr but in a totally different manner, the importance
of measuring operations.
WHAT DID LOUIS DE BROGLIE REALLY SAY ABOVE? OUR OWN COMMENTS
Please note our statement on how we use the phrase "pilot wave
theory" in the little note we put on top of all this.
Did the de Broglie of the 1950s understand nonlocality? The word
'nonlocality' became fashionable only long after J.S.Bell (in
taking apart the hidden assumptions in Von Neumann's proof) in the
1960s showed that the assumption of locality must be negated in
order to have a hidden variable interpretation of quantum theory;
Bell then went on to point out the importance of Bohm's work; and
subsequent research by Alain Aspect and others in the 1970s and
onwards showed that (apart from questions of interpretation),
entanglement has macroscopic effects and cannot be regarded as
merely a mathematical fiction.
It is certain that de Broglie of the 1980s understood and
accepted nonlocality. It is perhaps not so that he wanted to
push any such point in his 1950s work. It is in any case clear
that the pilot wave in three dimensions can exhibit nonlocal or
entangled, and also coherent, behaviour, in a way that's
compatible both with the work of de Broglie and with bohmian
mechanics. The fact that the wave, as seen by de Broglie,
exists (also) in three dimensional space doesn't preclude
the possibility of entanglement, as long as our whole reality
picture isn't confined to just the manifest dimensions.
As to young de Broglie's relationship to the somewhat
older Bohr: de Broglie, as one of the five top physicists
in the first half of the twentieth century, was said to be
in bed, nursing a headache, when Bohr, inside Bohr's
venerable institute in Copenhagen, went to his room and
pushed him (according to W. Heisenberg in a diary that
Heisenberg published after WWII), for hours, until de Broglie
gave up pursuing the pilot wave interpretation. According to
the present book by de Broglie, he never gave it up, he
merely regarded it as unfinished work, that had to be
worked more on in order to be presented more fully. And
it was Bohm's genius that set de Broglie aflame again, some
twenty or twenty-five years later, to begin to do just this.
Comments to the preface:
The distinction between what de Broglie calls a purely psychological
construct, Psi, and the wave u, is what he develops further on in
the book. de Broglie regards the probability densities, with its
many dimensions, not as having a direct reality in the physical
situation, even though the equation is there. Bohm, on the other
hand, chooses to attribute reality here; and as such, Bohm's view
of the reality of quantum situation at once calls for complexities
of a daunting kind in the image. They agree that there's a reality
to the particle and its position variables also when they are not
subject to measurement, but they disagree in what is around it. The
wave u is simpler in terms of visualisation than Psi. Bohm wants
Psi to be real; de Broglie wants Psi to be a calculated inference
with only u to be real. This opens for variations in how
one interprets the connection between particle and pilot wave, a
point made by some physicists but so far understood by very few.
It is a point that is of vital importance when one realises that
formalisms cannot be the theory itself, rather our ideas of reality
compose the theory, with formalisms as illustrations only of some
aspects of it.
As for agreement with Einstein's concepts--here de Broglie refers
to the desire of Einstein, shared with Karl R Popper and indeed a
large portion of those engaging in the theory of science, that
science, first and foremost, is about picturing reality and offering
formalisms so as to reason around these pictures and so as to
check predictions also, but not so that the formalism is taken to
be the theory itself.
On the other hand, it is well known, and has been ever since the
work by J.S.Bell in the 1960s, that nonlocality--entanglement--a
feature of quantum wholeness or coherence in which the speed of
light is not respected--are more or less part of quantum theory--
implicitly in all versions, but more explicitly in the pilot
wave type of interpretations; and, moreover, that this nonlocality
feature is at odds with the picture of reality that Einstein sought
to implement throughout all essential branches of physics. Einstein
called it a 'ghosthly action-at-a-distance'. While nonlocality
need not imply any signal transmission, due to fluctuations that
impede on signals relayed nonlocally, and thus may not in terms
of formalism contradict Einstein's formal postulates, it is
a foreign object in the vision of an only locally interacting
field that Einstein sought to implement. As many physicists have
further noted, nonlocality is a term that implies that distances
are covered not just faster than light, but at no time at all,
and while there's not any empirics as yet to indicate that
nonlocality should be considered something of an overstatement,
a modified quantum theory in the future, with modified
predictions, relating to superb new empirical instruments, may
succeed in producing discernment in this area, and may call for
a qualification in the use of the word 'nonlocal'.
But, back to Louis de Broglie's ideas here: the disagreement
with the spirit of Einstein's theories is more profound in the
de Broglie/Bohm line of development, than in the Heisenberg,
Bohr, Born line of thinking, since this feature of action-at-
a-distance is more explicitly present. However, since Einstein's
formalisms and approach to visualizing reality have different
starting-points than quantum theory, by and large, seeing these
theories together is formally very complex; but thanks to much
work by many physicists, some formal unification at some levels
have taken place between the Copenhagen Interpretation of
quantum theory and features of Einstein's General Relativity.
This type of intense work has not yet been put into any of the
pilot wave interpretations, at the time of writing this [2016].
And so, this has sometimes been used as an argument against the
bohmian mechanics--that it is both more explicitly against
Einstein's theories (even though the latter have had a very
broad range of confirmations and few disconfirmations)--and also
formally, less easy to tie in with Einstein's work.
At heart of this particular conflict with Einstein's work
is the idea of reality, and, if we elevate the ideas into
critical attention, for the moment looking away from formalisms
(as we should, since the theories in any case are not reducible
to mere formalism), we must, as David Bohm repeatedly did, ask
whether we should not regard Einstein's vision of reality as
something which is an appearance rather than the deep reality,
something which is an outcome of a reality that is fundamentally
not a process of a speed-of-light organised locally interacting
field. Bohm suggested, at a very general level, that quantum
theory broadly calls for a 'new order' in our visualisation of
reality, and this broad metaphysical understanding is indeed
compatible with many branches of development in more recent
physics. This is also compatible with where we might want to
take Louis de Broglie's pilot wave theory and where we might
want to take bohmian mechanics.
Thus, for instance, one can imagine that the speed of light
is an organising principle of sorts, where processes deeper
and faster than that are at works to give rise to the manifest
particles and waves. When, in a broad range of examples, only
local forces are found, that is due to a certain feature of
this deeper reality; but when there are phenomena of coherence
and entanglement over distance, this is simply another feature
of this deeper reality, and perhaps, in a sense, more near
this deeper reality. Einstein's picture is then regarded as
not absolutely true, but rather a visualisation of how things
tend to be when quantum coherence can be disregarded. Quantum
coherence may however not be just one phenomenon, for we are
never at any point in mere scientific theorising over found
empirics where we can with certainty say, "this is the final
type of process, there is nothing more to it than this." It
may be, and indeed it is the view of this writer (made
explicit in the Super-Model Theory), that quantum physics is
but a flicker of a flicker of a vastly different reality;
however, as it stretches rather to the maximum what the
technology of today can do fine measurements on, it is
unrealistic that by applying a minimalist (Occam's Razor)
type of theory of science, we'll ever come to appreciate
much of such a theory. Instead, we must ask whether we can
find other features than empirical measurements (such as
human intuition at a direct, logical level) to distinguish
one proposal from another in terms of what is best to
assume.
In the last sentence of the foreword, de Broglie looks to
the future and considers the present proposals--including,
it seems, the whole of quantum mechanics--to be a mere
pathway to what he calls a "microphysics". Let us take
this seriously into consideration, all the more when we
appreciate that in global fashion, the word "quantum"
has been, and still is, something of a rave. Quantum
physics, theory, mechanics, may be just a pathway, to a
microphysics in which different concepts are found to be
essential. And let us be clear that what de Broglie's
ideas of physics cohere with Einstein and he would not
put his signature on a physics which is merely a loose
collection ideas vaguely explaining some dense equations
that, for some reason or another, seem to work. The latter
type of physics--string theory is a recent example--is but
a furthering of the Heisenberg-Bohr-Born attitude that
de Broglie, along with both Einstein and Schroedinger,
and of course along with Bohm, Bell and a host of others,
find worthy of severe criticism as candidate physics.
String theories and other theories whose metaphors and
ideas flutter lightly around heavy formalisms are not
de Broglie's "true microphysics of the future". These are
but the logical consequence of the movement away from
a natural visualisation of the world along the lines
that Bohr, Born and Heisenberg argued for, more out of
respect for Einstein's principle of the limits of the
speed of light, than out of a metaphysical deliberation
to rob human theorising of a reality picture.
Comments to quotes from chapter III and onwards:
One might argue that Louis de Broglie seems needlessly
'tied up' to what we in this age of computation over
matrices of many dimensions and with so many many-
dimensional theories and forms of metaphysics hanging
over humanity in a sort of creative cloud, could
consider an 'old school' form of liking of three
dimensional space. But no matter how accustomed we
get to the phrase 'many dimensions', the fact
remains that imagining a wave in three dimension
is simpler and more intuitively obvious than
imagining it in a space that has as many dimensions
as their are particles, to take one example. And,
thinkers in theory of science, from Popper to Quine
and beyond, and before them, have always put a premium
on simplicity. If it is--and Louis de Broglie seems to
suggest that it is--possible to visualize a wave in
three dimensions in such a manner as to give rise to
the probability densities associated with Psi, then
by all means our theory of reality should, given the
candidate of this 3d wave and the many-dimensional
Psi wave in configuration space, prefer that which,
all other things being similar, is most simple.
In that way, it's not a question of being 'old school'
when three dimensions are brought in: it is rather a
question of sticking to Einstein's axiom that science
is chiefly an activity of our imagination, looking for
beauty and correlations in our imaginary map of
reality, and only then coming up with equations.
And so, in discerning the wave that gives rise to
the Psi wave as connected more to reality while the
Psi wave is an artefact of our formalisms, he is
indicating his chief disagreement, as I read him
and as I read Bohm, with what is now called bohmian
mechanics. He agrees with Bohm in the fundamental
pursuit for a theory that relates to the reality, or
the ontology, beyond the equations: but disagrees
in how this reality should be related to the
formalisms that we have. In his view, we ought to
have something simpler than what Bohm suggests in
order to account for the whole range of phenomena,
which in modern language, after John Bell's work
in the 1960s, is also called 'nonlocal' phenomena.
It's important to realize that de Broglie
nevertheless regards the whole idea of giving
particles position values and such in terms of
what is sometimes called 'hidden variables' (in
order to respect Heisenberg's uncertainty relation),
as entirely the right stuff. He agrees with Bohm
also in the way Bohm treats the measurement
situation--by means of a mutual transformation
between the measured objected and the measuring
instrument in a way that, due to the entanglements
and Planck's constant h--and as such
congratulates Bohm upon solving what the young
de Broglie himself couldn't do with his early
pilot wave theory. The ripe, post 1952 de Broglie
pilot wave theory is however incorporating this
part of Bohm's work and diverges in the aforesaid
manner in the reality picture.
This difference, as said, may be considered
less important than the grand question of whether
the Copenhagen Interpretation got its main
metaphysics wrong or not: but I disagree. It is
exactly in these little questions that we may come
up with essential differences that, at some point,
may be significant in providing instances of
confirmation and of disconfirmation so as to select
between these theories, in one way or another. The
little differences become great the moment we have
new forms of measurements involved, alongside new
proposed variations of the theories in various
directions. (My own proposed super-model theory is
an intuitive summary of a worldview that incorporates
the de Broglie pilot wave interpretation alongside
a number of other assumptions on a wholly different
set of underlaying premises.)
LINK SECTION
Link #1: The translation to English in 1960 of de Broglie's 1956 book
was published (see info above) by Elsevier Pub. Co., Amsterdam; New York,
and has this listing at www.worldcat.org. The copyright for the above
excerpts are also to Elsevier, in case of anyone wanting to include
them in the format of such as a book, or reproduce these excerpts in
any massive way. This, then, would help, alongside Link#3, to get
you in contact with copyright holders of the material:
http://www.worldcat.org/title/non-linear-wave-mechanics-a-causal-interpretation/oclc/10505307
Link #2: de Broglie's article from 1953, translated to English,
where he discusses some of the points more clearly elucidated
in his 1956 book, which in excerpts is given above.
The Interpretation of Wave Mechanics with the help of Waves with Singular Regions
The paper appeared in a collection of papers entitled
Scientific Papers Presented to Max Born
on his retirment from the Tait Chair of Natural Philosophy
in the University of Edinburgh,
published in 1953 (Oliver and Boyd).
http://arxiv.org/abs/1005.4534#
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1005.4534v1.pdf
Link #3:
Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie has a number of
articles in original French and some translations, and
contact info for the copyright holders of the written
material of Louis de Broglie. For any commercial or massive
redistribution of the above quotes, one must contact the
Louis de Broglie Foundation first, and one should find
contact info through the following link:
http://aflb.ensmp.fr/AFLB-Web/en-annales-index.htm
Link #4:
Next article is a translation of a french article de
Broglie wrote decades later (he died in the late 1980s),
where he, among other things, declares that he stands
firm on the postulate that the pilot wave interpretation
of quantum phenomena is for him more correct than the
other interpretations.
Interpretation of quantum mechanics by the double solution theory,
Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie, Vol. 12, No. 4, 1987.
http://aflb.ensmp.fr/AFLB-classiques/aflb124p001.pdf
Link #5: Next is an article written by David Bohm and Basil Hiley
where the points of agreement between the approach of Bohm and
de Broglie are emphasised. This is a very good introduction to
bohmian mechanics, and Hiley, C.Dewdney and others helped this
by contributing with appealing computer plottings of quantum
potential and possible particle trajectories. Considering the
rough time Bohm's causal interpretation had had, one can
understand that agreements are, at this stage, what is pointed
out. However, it is severely incomplete as far as presentation
of Louis de Broglie's own revised pilot theory goes, even though
it refers to the 1956 book of de Broglie, in that the difference
in the reality picture and the interpretations of the formalisms
are not elaborated upon, but rather underplayed. This I can say
even as I continue to warmly support the work by my friend the
late David Bohm, and how it is followed up by Basil Hiley (whom
I have also had the pleasure of meeting) and many others in a
steadily increasing flood of interesting publications all over
the world, in about every scientific journals and magazine there
is, at many universities (not in the least in Germany), and
by more and more books. The change in the scientific community
from how I remember it about when I visited Bohm at Birkbeck,
in 1986 and twice more (before we invited him in Oslo for a
weekend seminar on his favorite theme of 'Dialogue'), is quite
startling. And work such as by the canadian A.Goldberg, both
on the empirical and theoretical level, to dismiss the idea
that the trajectories in bohmian mechanics are anywhere near
'surreal', has contributed to a surge of renewed interest.
Anyway, here's the promised article info and what should be
a good working link to a pdf of this important 1982 article:
Title: The de Broglie Pilot Wave Theory and the Further Development
of New Insights Arising Out of It
by David Bohm and Basil Hiley
in: Foundations of Physics, Vol. 12, No. 10, 1982.
http://scalettar.physics.ucdavis.edu/p298/pilotwavetheory.pdf
Questions? Email srw at avenuege.com